Algebraic logic
In mathematical logic, algebraic logic is the reasoning obtained by manipulating equations with free variables.
What is now usually called classical algebraic logic focuses on the identification and algebraic description of
Works in the more recent abstract algebraic logic (AAL) focus on the process of algebraization itself, like classifying various forms of algebraizability using the Leibniz operator (Czelakowski 2003).
Calculus of relations
A homogeneous
"The basic operations are set-theoretic union, intersection and complementation, the relative multiplication, and conversion."[1]
The conversion refers to the converse relation that always exists, contrary to function theory. A given relation may be represented by a logical matrix; then the converse relation is represented by the transpose matrix. A relation obtained as the composition of two others is then represented by the logical matrix obtained by matrix multiplication using Boolean arithmetic.
Example
An example of calculus of relations arises in erotetics, the theory of questions. In the universe of utterances there are statements S and questions Q. There are two relations π and α from Q to S: q α a holds when a is a direct answer to question q. The other relation, q π p holds when p is a presupposition of question q. The converse relation πT runs from S to Q so that the composition πTα is a homogeneous relation on S.[2] The art of putting the right question to elicit a sufficient answer is recognized in Socratic method dialogue.
Functions
The description of the key binary relation properties has been formulated with the calculus of relations. The univalence property of functions describes a relation R that satisfies the formula where I is the identity relation on the range of R. The injective property corresponds to univalence of , or the formula where this time I is the identity on the domain of R.
But a univalent relation is only a partial function, while a univalent total relation is a function. The formula for totality is Charles Loewner and Gunther Schmidt use the term mapping for a total, univalent relation.[3][4]
The facility of
using for the complement of relation R. These equivalences provide alternative formulas for univalent relations (), and total relations (). Therefore, mappings satisfy the formula Schmidt uses this principle as "slipping below negation from the left".[5] For a mapping f,Abstraction
The relation algebra structure, based in set theory, was transcended by Tarski with axioms describing it. Then he asked if every algebra satisfying the axioms could be represented by a set relation. The negative answer[6] opened the frontier of abstract algebraic logic.[7][8][9]
Algebras as models of logics
Algebraic logic treats algebraic structures, often bounded lattices, as models (interpretations) of certain logics, making logic a branch of order theory.
In algebraic logic:
- Variables are tacitly universe of discourse. There are no existentially quantified variables or open formulas;
- Terms are built up from variables using primitive and defined operations. There are no connectives;
- Formulas, built from terms in the usual way, can be equated if they are logically equivalent. To express a tautology, equate a formula with a truth value;
- The rules of proof are the substitution of equals for equals[clarification needed], and uniform replacement. Modus ponens remains valid, but is seldom employed.
In the table below, the left column contains one or more
Algebraic formalisms going beyond first-order logic in at least some respects include:
- Combinatory logic, having the expressive power of set theory;
- ZFC.
Logical system | Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra |
---|---|
Classical sentential logic
|
Boolean algebra |
Intuitionistic propositional logic | Heyting algebra |
Łukasiewicz logic | MV-algebra |
Modal logic K | Modal algebra |
Lewis's S4
|
Interior algebra |
Lewis's monadic predicate logic
|
Monadic Boolean algebra |
First-order logic | Complete Boolean algebra, polyadic algebra, predicate functor logic |
First-order logic with equality | Cylindric algebra |
Set theory | Combinatory logic, relation algebra |
History
Algebraic logic is, perhaps, the oldest approach to formal logic, arguably beginning with a number of memoranda
Modern mathematical logic began in 1847, with two pamphlets whose respective authors were
In 1903
Some writings by Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem on algebraic logic appeared after the 1910–13 publication of Principia Mathematica, and Tarski revived interest in relations with his 1941 essay "On the Calculus of Relations".[9]
According to Helena Rasiowa, "The years 1920-40 saw, in particular in the Polish school of logic, researches on non-classical propositional calculi conducted by what is termed the logical matrix method. Since logical matrices are certain abstract algebras, this led to the use of an algebraic method in logic."[17]
Brady (2000) discusses the rich historical connections between algebraic logic and model theory. The founders of model theory, Ernst Schröder and Leopold Loewenheim, were logicians in the algebraic tradition. Alfred Tarski, the founder of set theoretic model theory as a major branch of contemporary mathematical logic, also:
- Initiated abstract algebraic logic with relation algebras[9]
- Invented cylindric algebra
- Co-discovered Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra.
In the practice of the calculus of relations,
Leibniz had no influence on the rise of algebraic logic because his logical writings were little studied before the Parkinson and Loemker translations. Our present understanding of Leibniz as a logician stems mainly from the work of Wolfgang Lenzen, summarized in Lenzen (2004). To see how present-day work in logic and metaphysics can draw inspiration from, and shed light on, Leibniz's thought, see Zalta (2000).
See also
References
- ISBN 978-0-8218-5035-0.
- ^ Eugene Freeman (1934) The Categories of Charles Peirce, page 10, Open Court Publishing Company, quote: By retaining the realistic presuppositions of the plain man concerning the genuineness of external reality, Peirce is able to reinforce the precarious defenses of a conventionalistic theory of nature with the powerful armament of common-sense realism.
- ISBN 3-540-56254-0
- ISBN 978-0-521-76268-7
- ISBN 978-3-319-74451-3
- MR 0037278.
- Vaughn Pratt The Origins of the Calculus of Relations, from Stanford University
- ^ Roger Maddux (1991) "The Origin of Relation Algebras in the Development and Axiomatization of the Calculus of Relations", Studia Logica 50: 421-55
- ^ doi:10.2307/2268577
- ^ Clarence Lewis (1918) A Survey of Symbolic Logic, University of California Press, second edition 1932, Dover edition 1960
- ^ George Boole, The Mathematical Analysis of Logic, Being an Essay towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning (London, England: Macmillan, Barclay, & Macmillan, 1847).
- Hathi Trust
- ^ Alexander Macfarlane (1879), Principles of the Algebra of Logic, via Internet Archive
- Christine Ladd (1883), On the Algebra of Logic via Google Books
- B. G. Teubner via Internet Archive
- ^ B. Russell (1903) The Principles of Mathematics
- ISBN 0-88385-109-1
Sources
- Brady, Geraldine (2000). From Peirce to Skolem: A Neglected Chapter in the History of Logic. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Mathematics. Amsterdam, Netherlands: North-Holland/Elsevier Science BV. ISBN 9780080532028.
- Czelakowski, Janusz (2003). "Review: Algebraic Methods in Philosophical Logic by J. Michael Dunn and Gary M. Hardegree". The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 9. Association for Symbolic Logic, Cambridge University Press. JSTOR 3094793.
- Lenzen, Wolfgang, 2004, "Leibniz’s Logic" in Gabbay, D., and Woods, J., eds., Handbook of the History of Logic, Vol. 3: The Rise of Modern Logic from Leibniz to Frege. North-Holland: 1-84.
- Loemker, Leroy (1969) [First edition 1956], Leibniz: Philosophical Papers and Letters (2nd ed.), Reidel.
- Parkinson, G.H.R (1966). Leibniz: Logical Papers. Oxford University Press.
- Zalta, E. N., 2000, "A (Leibnizian) Theory of Concepts," Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse / Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 3: 137-183.
Further reading
- J. Michael Dunn; Gary M. Hardegree (2001). Algebraic Methods in Philosophical Logic. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-853192-0. Good introduction for readers with prior exposure to non-classical logics but without much background in order theory and/or universal algebra; the book covers these prerequisites at length. This book however has been criticized for poor and sometimes incorrect presentation of AAL results. Review by Janusz Czelakowski
- ISBN 978-0-7923-7126-7. Draft.
- Ramon Jansana (2011), "Propositional Consequence Relations and Algebraic Logic". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Mainly about abstract algebraic logic.
- Stanley Burris (2015), "The Algebra of Logic Tradition". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Willard Quine, 1976, "Algebraic Logic and Predicate Functors" pages 283 to 307 in The Ways of Paradox, Harvard University Press.
Historical perspective
- Ivor Grattan-Guinness, 2000. The Search for Mathematical Roots. Princeton University Press.
- ISBN 0444885439