Edmund Gettier

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.
Edmund Gettier
Baltimore, Maryland, U.S.
DiedMarch 23, 2021(2021-03-23) (aged 93)
EraContemporary philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolAnalytic philosophy
Doctoral advisorNorman Malcolm
Main interests
Epistemology
Notable ideas
Gettier problem

Edmund Lee Gettier III (

philosopher at the University of Massachusetts Amherst. He is best known for his article written in 1963: "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?",[1] which has generated an extensive philosophical literature trying to respond to what became known as the Gettier problem
.

Life

Edmund Lee Gettier III was born on October 31, 1927, in

Gettier obtained his

PhD in philosophy from Cornell University in 1961 with a dissertation on “Bertrand Russell’s Theories of Belief” written under the supervision of Norman Malcolm.[2][3]

Gettier taught philosophy at Wayne State University from 1957 until 1967[2] initially as an Instructor, then as an assistant professor, and, latterly, as an associate professor.[4] His philosophical colleagues at Wayne State included, among others, Alvin Plantinga and Héctor-Neri Castaneda.[5]

In the academic year of 1964–65, he held a postdoctoral

Bas C. Van Fraasen[7] and published his first and only book review of John Passmore's Philosophical Reasoning.[8]

In 1967, Gettier was recruited to the faculty of philosophy at the University of Massachusetts Amherst, being promoted to full professor there in 1972.[4] He taught there until his retirement, as Professor Emeritus, in 2001.[4]

Gettier died on March 23, 2021, aged 93.[4]

Gettier's fame rests on a three-page article, published in

Clarence Irving Lewis and his student Roderick Chisholm. Gettier's article offered counterexamples to this account in the form of cases in which subjects had true beliefs that were also justified, but for which the beliefs were true for reasons unrelated to the justification. Some philosophers, however, thought the account of knowledge as justified true belief had already been questioned in a general way by the work of Wittgenstein.[citation needed] (Later, a similar argument was found in the papers of Bertrand Russell.[9]
)

Work

Gettier problem

Gettier provides several examples of beliefs that are both true and justified, but that we should not intuitively term knowledge. Cases of this sort are now termed "Gettier (counter-)examples". Because Gettier's criticism of the justified true belief model is systemic, other authors have imagined increasingly fantastical counterexamples. For example: I am watching the men's Wimbledon Final, and John McEnroe is playing Jimmy Connors, it is match point, and McEnroe wins. I say to myself: "John McEnroe is this year's men's champion at Wimbledon". Unbeknownst to me, however, the BBC were experiencing a broadcasting fault and so had broadcast a tape of last year's final, when McEnroe also beat Connors. I had been watching last year's Wimbledon final, so I believed that McEnroe had bested Connors. But at that same time, in real life, McEnroe was repeating last year's victory and besting Connors! So my belief that McEnroe bested Connors to become this year's Wimbledon champion is true, and I had good reason to believe so (my belief was justified) — and yet, there is a sense in which I could not really have claimed to "know" that McEnroe had bested Connors because I was only accidentally right that McEnroe beat Connors — my belief was not based on the right kind of justification.

Gettier inspired a great deal of work by philosophers attempting to recover a working

definition of knowledge
. Major responses include:

  • Gettier's use of "justification" is too general, and only some kinds of justification count.
  • Gettier's examples do not count as justification at all, and only some kinds of evidence are justificatory.
  • Knowledge must have a fourth condition, such as "no false premises" or "indefeasibility".
  • Robert Nozick suggests knowledge must consist of justified true belief that is "truth-tracking" — a belief such that if it was revealed to be false, it would not have been believed, and conversely.
  • Colin McGinn suggests that knowledge is atomic (it is not divisible into smaller components). We have knowledge when we have knowledge, and an accurate definition of knowledge may even contain the word "knowledge".[10]

A 2001 study by Weinberg, Nichols, and Stich suggests that the effect of the Gettier problem varies by culture. In particular, people from Western countries seem more likely to agree with the judgments described in the story than do those from East Asia.[11] Subsequent studies were unable to replicate these results.[12]

Complete works

See also

References

External links