Large cardinal
In the mathematical field of
There is a rough convention that results provable from ZFC alone may be stated without hypotheses, but that if the proof requires other assumptions (such as the existence of large cardinals), these should be stated. Whether this is simply a linguistic convention, or something more, is a controversial point among distinct philosophical schools (see Motivations and epistemic status below).
A large cardinal axiom is an axiom stating that there exists a cardinal (or perhaps many of them) with some specified large cardinal property.
Most working set theorists believe that the large cardinal axioms that are currently being considered are
There is no generally agreed precise definition of what a large cardinal property is, though essentially everyone agrees that those in the list of large cardinal properties are large cardinal properties.
Partial definition
A necessary condition for a property of cardinal numbers to be a large cardinal property is that the existence of such a cardinal is not known to be inconsistent with
Hierarchy of consistency strength
A remarkable observation about large cardinal axioms is that they appear to occur in strict
- Unless ZFC is inconsistent, ZFC+A1 is consistent if and only if ZFC+A2 is consistent;
- ZFC+A1 proves that ZFC+A2 is consistent; or
- ZFC+A2 proves that ZFC+A1 is consistent.
These are mutually exclusive, unless one of the theories in question is actually inconsistent.
In case 1, we say that A1 and A2 are
The observation that large cardinal axioms are linearly ordered by consistency strength is just that, an observation, not a theorem. (Without an accepted definition of large cardinal property, it is not subject to proof in the ordinary sense.) Also, it is not known in every case which of the three cases holds.
The order of consistency strength is not necessarily the same as the order of the size of the smallest witness to a large cardinal axiom. For example, the existence of a huge cardinal is much stronger, in terms of consistency strength, than the existence of a supercompact cardinal, but assuming both exist, the first huge is smaller than the first supercompact.
Motivations and epistemic status
Large cardinals are understood in the context of the
Thus, from a certain point of view held by many set theorists (especially those inspired by the tradition of the
This point of view is by no means universal among set theorists. Some formalists would assert that standard set theory is by definition the study of the consequences of ZFC, and while they might not be opposed in principle to studying the consequences of other systems, they see no reason to single out large cardinals as preferred. There are also realists who deny that ontological maximalism is a proper motivation, and even believe that large cardinal axioms are false. And finally, there are some who deny that the negations of large cardinal axioms are restrictive, pointing out that (for example) there can be a transitive set model in L that believes there exists a measurable cardinal, even though L itself does not satisfy that proposition.
See also
Notes
- ISBN 0-19-853241-5.
- ^ Joel, Hamkins (2022-12-24). "Does anyone still seriously doubt the consistency of ZFC?". MathOverflow.
References
- Drake, F. R. (1974). Set Theory: An Introduction to Large Cardinals (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics; V. 76). Elsevier Science Ltd. ISBN 0-444-10535-2.
- ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
- ISBN 3-540-00384-3.
- Kanamori, Akihiro; Magidor, M. (1978), "The evolution of large cardinal axioms in set theory" (PDF), Higher Set Theory, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 669, Springer Berlin / Heidelberg, pp. 99–275, ISBN 978-3-540-08926-1, retrieved September 25, 2022
- JSTOR 2274520.
- Maddy, Penelope (1988). "Believing the Axioms, II". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 53 (3): 736–764. S2CID 16544090.
- arXiv:math/0211397.
- .
- Woodin, W. Hugh (2001). "The continuum hypothesis, part II". Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 48 (7): 681–690.