Ousia

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.

Ousia (

trinitarian doctrine.[2]

The Ancient Greek term θεία ουσία (theia ousia; divine essence) was translated in Latin as essentia or substantia, and hence in English as essence or substance.[3]

Etymology

The term οὐσία is an

early Christian theologian Tertullian favored the use of substantia over essentia, while Augustine of Hippo and Boethius took the opposite stance, preferring the use of essentia as designation for οὐσία.[5][6] Some of the most prominent Latin authors, like Hilary of Poitiers, noted that those variants were often being used with different meanings.[7] Some modern authors also suggest that the Ancient Greek term οὐσία is properly translated as essentia (essence), while substantia has a wider spectrum of meanings.[8]

From οὐσία (essence), philosophical and theological term οὐσιότης (essentiality) was also derived. It was used by

Platonists, like Alcinous, as designation for one of the basic properties of divinity or godhead.[9]

Philosophy

primary essences) in the Categories as that which is neither said of nor in any subject, e.g., "this human" in particular, or "this ox". The genera in biology and other natural kinds are substances in a secondary sense, as universals, formally defined by the essential qualities of the primary substances; i.e., the individual members of those kinds.[10]

In Book IV of Metaphysics Aristotle explores the nature and attributes of being (ousia). Aristotle divides the things that there are, or "beings," into categories. Aristotle calls these substances and argues that there are many senses in which a thing may be said "to be" but it is related to one central point and is ambiguous.[11]

ontologically based and if the primary substances did not exist then it would be impossible for other things to exist.[12] The other things are regarded as the secondary substances (also known as accidents). Secondary substances are thus ontologically dependent on substances.[12]

In Metaphysics, Aristotle states that everything which is healthy is related to health (primary substance) as in one sense because it preserves health and in the other because it is capable of it. Without the primary substance (health) we would not be able to have the secondary substances (anything related to health). While all the secondary substances are deemed "to be" it is in relation to the primary substance.[11]

The question, what is being, is seeking an answer to something "that is." A contemporary example in rhetoric would be to look at a color. Using white as an example, when we define a color, we define it by association. Snow is white. Paper is white. A cow is white. But what is white? While we are saying things that are white, we are not defining what white is without qualification. Ousia is thus the answer to the question of "what is being" when the question is without qualification. The unqualified answer of what is white is the ousia of white.

Much later,

hypostasis denoting existence.[13]

In the 20th century, the Australian philosopher

mind-body dualism which underlies much of the philosophical materialism which prevails within the modern world.[16][17]

Christian theology

The concept of θεία οὐσία (theia ousia; divine essence) is one of the most important concepts in

Early Church Fathers during the first centuries of Christian History. Central debates over the doctrinal use and meaning of οὐσία were held during the 4th century, and also continued later, some of them lasting up to the present day.[2]

New Testament

The word ousia is used in the New Testament only in relation to the substance in the sense of goods, twice in the parable of the Prodigal Son where the son asked his father to divide to him his inheritance, and then wasted it on riotous living.[18][19]

An apparently related word,

epiousios (affixing the prefix epi- to the word), is used in the Lord's Prayer, but nowhere else in the scriptures. Elsewhere, it was believed to be present in one papyrus (a list of expenses) among expenses for chick-peas, straw, etc., and for material.[20] In 1998, according to a xerographic copy of a papyrus found in the Yale Papyrus Collection (from the Beinecke Rare Book and Manuscript Library) inventory 19 (a.k.a. P.C.+YBR inv 19), it was suggested that the document had been transcribed differently from other early manuscripts and that the actual word used in that particular papyrus was elaiou, meaning "oil".[21]

Early Christianity

homoousios (same essence) because it originated in pagan Greek philosophy.[citation needed] John Chapman's Catholic Encyclopedia entry for Paul of Samosata
states:

It must be regarded as certain that the council, which condemned Paul, rejected the term homoousios; but, naturally, only in a false sense, used by Paul; not, it seems, because he meant by it a unity of Hypostasis in the Trinity (so St. Hilary), but because he intended, by it, a common essence, out of which both Father and Son proceeded, or which it divided between them – so St. Basil and St. Athanasius; but the question is not clear. The objectors to the Nicene doctrine in the fourth century made copious use of this disapproval of the Nicene word by a famous council.[22]

In 325, the

Nicene creed
.

The generally agreed-upon meaning of ousia in

John Damascene gives the following definition of the conceptual value of the two terms in his Dialectic: Ousia is a thing that exists by itself, and which has need of nothing else for its consistency. Again, ousia is all that subsists by itself and which has not its being in another.[24]

See also

References

  1. ^ url=https://en.m.wiktionary.org/wiki/ousia
  2. ^ a b Athanasopoulos & Schneider 2013.
  3. .
  4. ^ Conte, G.B.: "Latin Literature: a history" (1987) p. 199
  5. ^ Owens 1951, pp. 137–154.
  6. ^ Brown 1996, p. 276.
  7. ^ Weedman 2007.
  8. ^ Pásztori-Kupán 2006, pp. 59–60.
  9. ^ Bracht 2009, p. 111.
  10. ^ Cohen, S. Marc (2004). "Lecture on Categories". Primary substances are fundamental in that "if they did not exist it would be impossible for any of the other things to exist." [Categories, 2b5]
  11. ^ a b Aristotle. "Metaphysics" (PDF).
  12. ^ a b Cohen, Mark. "Substances" (PDF).
  13. ^ Heidegger 1996.
  14. ^ Murphy, Jeffrie "G. Berkeley and the Metaphor of Mental Substance." Ratio 7 (1965):171, note 3.
  15. .
  16. .
  17. ^ "Berkeley Essay Prize Competition". www.sas.rochester.edu. Retrieved 2024-01-22.
  18. ^ Thomas Mozley The creed or a philosophy 1893 p. 303 "III 'Ousia' In The New Testament The only appearance of this word in the New Testament is in two successive verses of the Parable of the Prodigal Son. It there designates first the 'living' which the Prodigal Son compelled his father..."
  19. ^ "G3776 – ousia – Strong's Greek Lexicon (kjv)". Blue Letter Bible.
  20. ^ Kittel, G., Bromiley, G. W., & Friedrich, G. (Eds.). Theological dictionary of the New Testament (electronic ed., Vol. 2, pp. 590–591). Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.
  21. ^ Discussion on the B-Greek mailing list. 2005
  22. ^ John Chapman. "Catholic Encyclopedia: Paul of Samosata". www.newadvent.org.
  23. ^ Lossky 1976, p. 51.
  24. ^ Lossky 1976, p. 50.

Bibliography

External links

This page is based on the copyrighted Wikipedia article: Ousia. Articles is available under the CC BY-SA 3.0 license; additional terms may apply.Privacy Policy