Physical symbol system

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.
(Redirected from
Physical symbol systems hypothesis
)

A physical symbol system (also called a formal system) takes physical patterns (symbols), combining them into structures (expressions) and manipulating them (using processes) to produce new expressions.

The physical symbol system hypothesis (PSSH) is a position in the philosophy of artificial intelligence formulated by Allen Newell and Herbert A. Simon. They wrote:

"A physical symbol system has the

necessary and sufficient means for general intelligent action."[1]

This claim implies both that human thinking is a kind of symbol manipulation (because a symbol system is necessary for intelligence) and that machines can be intelligent (because a symbol system is

sufficient for intelligence).[2]

The idea has philosophical roots in

Hobbes (who claimed reasoning was "nothing more than reckoning"), Leibniz (who attempted to create a logical calculus of all human ideas), Hume (who thought perception could be reduced to "atomic impressions") and even Kant (who analyzed all experience as controlled by formal rules).[3] The latest version is called the computational theory of mind, associated with philosophers Hilary Putnam and Jerry Fodor.[4]

Examples

Examples of physical symbol systems include:

The physical symbol system hypothesis claims that both of these are also examples of physical symbol systems:

  • Intelligent human thought: the symbols are encoded in our brains. The expressions are thoughts. The processes are the mental operations of thinking.
  • English language: the symbols are words. The expressions are sentences. The processes are the mental operations that enable speaking, writing or reading.

Evidence for the hypothesis

Two lines of evidence suggested to Allen Newell and Herbert A. Simon that "symbol manipulation" was the essence of both human and machine intelligence: psychological experiments on human beings and the development of artificial intelligence programs.

Psychological experiments and computer models

Newell and Simon carried out psychological experiments that showed that, for difficult problems in logic, planning or any kind of "puzzle solving", people carefully proceeded step-by-step, considering several different possible ways forward, selected the most promising one, backing up when the possibility hit a dead end. Each possible solution was visualized with symbols, such as words, numbers or diagrams. This was "symbol manipulation" -- the people were iteratively exploring a formal system looking for a matching pattern that solved the puzzle.[5][6][7] Newell and Simon were able to simulate the step by step problem solving skills of people with computer programs; they created programs that used the same algorithms as people and were able to solve the same problems.

This type of research, using both experimental psychology and computer models, was called "cognitive simulation" by Hubert Dreyfus.[8] Their work was profoundly influential: it contributed to the cognitive revolution of the 1960s, the founding of the field of cognitive science and cognitivism in psychology.

This line of research suggested that human problem solving consisted primarily of the manipulation of high-level symbols.

Artificial intelligence programs in the 1950s and 60s

In the early decades of AI research there were many very successful programs that used high-level symbol processing. These programs were very successful, demonstrating skills that many people at the time had assumed were impossible for machines, such as solving

STUDENT), proving theorems in logic (Logic Theorist), learning to play competitive checkers (Arthur Samuel's checkers), and communicating in natural language (ELIZA, SHRDLU).[9][10] [11]

The success of these programs suggested that symbol processing systems could simulate any intelligent action.

Clarifications

The physical symbol systems hypothesis becomes trivial, incoherent or irrelevant unless we recognize a distinction between "digitized signals" and "symbols", between

and intelligent behavior.

Semantic symbols vs. dynamic signals

The physical symbol system hypothesis is only interesting if we restrict the "symbols" to things that have a recognizable

. These may technically be symbols, but it is not always possible to determine exactly what the symbols are standing for. This is not what Newell and Simon had in mind, and the argument becomes trivial if we include them.

Touretzky and Pomerleau write that if symbols and signals are the same thing, then "[s]ufficiency is a given, unless one is a dualist or some other sort of mystic, because physical symbol systems are Turing-universal."[12] The widely accepted Church–Turing thesis holds that any Turing-universal system can simulate any conceivable process that can be digitized, given enough time and memory. Since any digital computer is Turing-universal, any digital computer can, in theory, simulate anything that can be digitized to a sufficient level of precision, including the behavior of intelligent organisms. The necessary condition of the physical symbol systems hypothesis can likewise be finessed, since we are willing to accept almost any signal as a form of "symbol" and all intelligent biological systems have signal pathways.[12]

The same issue applies to the unidentified numbers that appear in the matrixes of a

neural network or a support vector machine. These programs are using the same mathematics as a digitial simulation of a dynamical system, and is better understood as "dynamic system" than a "physical symbol system". Nils Nilsson wrote: "any physical process can be simulated to any desired degree of accuracy on a symbol-manipulating computer, but an account of such a simulation in terms of symbols, instead of signals, can be unmanageably cumbersome."[13]

General intelligence vs. "narrow" intelligence

The PSSH refers to "general intelligent action" -- that is, to every activity that we would consider "intelligent". Thus it is the claim that

narrow
" applications.

Artificial intelligence research has succeeded in developing many programs that are capable of intelligently solving particular problems. However, AI research has so far not been able to produce a system with artificial general intelligence -- the ability to solve a variety of novel problems, as human do. Thus, the criticism of the PSSH refers to the limits of AI in the future, and does not apply to any current research or programs.

Consciousness vs. intelligent action

The PSSH refers to "intelligent action" -- that is, the behavior of the machine -- it does not refer to the "mental states", "mind", "consciousness", or the "experiences" of the machine. "Consciousness", as far as neurology can determine, is not something that can deduced from the behavior of an agent: it is always possible that the machine is simulating the experience of consciousness, without actually experiencing it, similar to the way a perfectly written fictional character might simulate a person with consciousness.

Thus, the PSSH is not relevant to positions which refer to "mind" or "consciousness", such as

Strong AI hypothesis
:

The appropriately programmed computer with the right inputs and outputs would thereby have a mind in exactly the same sense human beings have minds.[14][15]

Evidence against the hypothesis

Nils Nilsson has identified four main "themes" or grounds in which the physical symbol system hypothesis has been attacked.[16]

  1. The "erroneous claim that the [physical symbol system hypothesis] lacks
    symbol grounding
    " which is presumed to be a requirement for general intelligent action.
  2. The common belief that AI requires non-symbolic processing (that which can be supplied by a connectionist architecture for instance).
  3. The common statement that the brain is simply not a computer and that "computation as it is currently understood, does not provide an appropriate model for intelligence".
  4. And last of all that it is also believed in by some that the brain is essentially mindless, most of what takes place are chemical reactions and that human intelligent behaviour is analogous to the intelligent behaviour displayed for example by ant colonies.

Evidence the brain does not always use symbols

If the human brain does not use symbolic reasoning to create intelligent behavior, then the necessary side of the hypothesis is false, and human intelligence is the counter-example.

Dreyfus

Hubert Dreyfus attacked the necessary condition of the physical symbol system hypothesis, calling it "the psychological assumption" and defining it thus:

  • The mind can be viewed as a device operating on bits of information according to formal rules.[17]

Dreyfus refuted this by showing that human intelligence and expertise depended primarily on unconscious instincts rather than conscious symbolic manipulation. Experts solve problems quickly by using their intuitions, rather than step-by-step trial and error searches. Dreyfus argued that these unconscious skills would never be captured in formal rules.[18]

Tversky and Kahnemann

Embodied cognition

ethics and philosophy depend on unconscious skills that derive from the body, and that conscious symbol manipulation is only a small part of our intelligence.[citation needed
]

Evidence that symbolic AI can't efficiently generate intelligence for all problems

It is impossible to prove that symbolic AI will never produce general intelligence, but if we can not find an efficient way to solve particular problems with symbolic AI, this is evidence that the sufficient side of the PSSH is unlikely to be true.

Intractability

Common sense knowledge, frame, qualification and ramification problems

Moravec's paradox

Evidence that sub-symbolic or neurosymbolic AI programs can generate intelligence

If sub-symbolic AI programs, such as deep learning, can intelligently solve problems, then this is evidence that the necessary side of the PSSH is false.

If hybrid approaches that combine symbolic AI with other approaches can efficiently solve a wider range of problems than either technique alone, this is evidence that the necessary side is true and the sufficiency side is false.

Brooks

MIT was able to build robots that had superior ability to move and survive without the use of symbolic reasoning at all. Brooks (and others, such as Hans Moravec
) discovered that our most basic skills of motion, survival, perception, balance and so on did not seem to require high-level symbols at all, that in fact, the use of high-level symbols was more complicated and less successful.

In a 1990 paper Elephants Don't Play Chess, robotics researcher Rodney Brooks took direct aim at the physical symbol system hypothesis, arguing that symbols are not always necessary since "the world is its own best model. It is always exactly up to date. It always has every detail there is to be known. The trick is to sense it appropriately and often enough."[19]

Connectionism and deep learning

In 2012 AlexNet, a deep learning network, outperformed all other programs in classifying images on ImageNet by a substantial margin. In the years since, deep learning has proved to be much more successful in many domains than symbolic AI.[citation needed]

Hybrid AI

Symbol grounding

See also

  • Artificial intelligence, situated approach
  • Artificial philosophy

Notes

  1. ^ Newell & Simon 1976, p. 116 and Russell & Norvig 2003, p. 18
  2. ^ Nilsson 2007, p. 1.
  3. ^ Dreyfus 1979, p. 156, Haugeland, pp. 15–44
  4. ^ Horst 2005
  5. ^ Newell, Shaw & Simon 1958.
  6. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 450–451.
  7. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 258–263.
  8. ^ Dreyfus 1979, pp. 130–148.
  9. ^ McCorduck 2004, pp. 243–252.
  10. ^ Crevier 1993, pp. 52–107.
  11. ^ Russell & Norvig 2021, pp. 19–21.
  12. ^ a b Reconstructing Physical Symbol Systems David S. Touretzky and Dean A. Pomerleau Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University Cognitive Science 18(2):345–353, 1994. https://www.cs.cmu.edu/~dst/pubs/simon-reply-www.ps.gz
  13. ^ Nilsson 2007, p. 10.
  14. ^ Searle 1999, p. [page needed].
  15. ^ Dennett 1991, p. 435.
  16. ^ Nilsson, p. 1.
  17. ^ Dreyfus 1979, p. 156
  18. ^ Dreyfus 1972, Dreyfus 1979, Dreyfus & Dreyfus 1986. See also Crevier 1993, pp. 120–132 and Hearn 2007, pp. 50–51
  19. ^ Brooks 1990, p. 3

References