Contemporary ethics

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.

Ethics is, in general terms, the study of right and wrong. It can look descriptively at moral behaviour and judgements; it can give practical advice (normative ethics), or it can analyse and theorise about the nature of morality and ethics.[1]

Contemporary study of ethics has many links with other disciplines in

meta-ethics is increasingly followed. Abstract theorizing has in many areas been replaced by experience-based research.[3]

Practical and theoretical areas

neurobiology are areas which have helped and been helped in progress in ethics.[4] Within philosophy, epistemology (or the study of how we know) has drawn closer to ethics.[5] This is in part due to the recognition that knowledge, like value and goodness, can be seen as a normative concept. The traditional analyses and definitions of knowledge have been shown to be unsound by the Gettier problem
.

New interest has flourished in meta-ethics.[6] This has in recent years developed as a recognised category proceeding from the work of Hume, G. E. Moore and the error theories of J. L. Mackie[7] who seeks a real basis, if any, for talk of values and right and wrong. Mackie is sceptical about solving the dilemma posed by the distinction between values and facts.

Reason vs intuition

The dominance of

Heidegger's work has become increasingly translated and interpreted in the Anglo-American sphere and the wisdom of always following reason is widely questioned.[9][10]

The

communitarian view of the social world. Reason and emotion are seen as more equal partners in human actions [12]

There remain major divergences of perspective, for example between continental and analytic approaches, and process/ pragmatism vs logical, a priori approaches.

Edmund Gettier wrote a short but influential article [13] showing that knowledge is not captured by a traditionally accepted reason based definitions. Pragmatism, and process philosophy in general, is increasingly adopted as a response to a constantly changing understanding of a dynamic world, both physically and in the realms of experiment and investigation.

Changed focus

Mackie (1977) states that increasing secularisation has meant that religion is not seen by many as the ground for deciding how we should act. Quine's critique [14] of the analytic–synthetic distinction has implications for morality (for example in the work of Kant). Logic is a diverse and apparently flexible branch of thought, rather than being thought to underlie mathematics and reasoning, as previously.

grand narratives
. Mackie (1977), in particular, saw this decline as undermining the legitimacy of traditional morality.

This has stimulated the development of both

value systems. As a result, there is growing acceptance of the plausibility of making decisions based on the context,[16] and the particular situation being considered, rather than by reference to principles. This move away from grand theory confirms earlier views of Adam Smith,[17]
who held that moral theories derived from moral actions rather than conversely.

Challenges remaining

Major challenges for ethics include the fact/value distinction,[18] the error theory which seems to undermine the reality [19] of moral claims[20][21] and apparent relativism[22][23] across cultures and eras. Some feel that the persistence of problems in ethics theory has led to an overall decline in the interest in working in the field of pure ethics as more opportunities arise in applied ethics and meta-ethics. Stephen Darwall et al[24] referred to "a genuinely new period in twentieth century ethics, the vigorous revival of metaethics coincidental with the emergence .. of a criticism of the enterprise of moral theory itself".

References

  1. ^ "Ethics [Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]". Iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 2012-08-15.
  2. ^ Almond, Brenda (ed. with D Hill),1991 Applied Philosophy: Morals and Metaphysics in Contemporary Debate London: Routledge.
  3. ^ Appiah, Kwame Anthony. (2008). Experiments in Ethics. Harvard University Press.
  4. .
  5. ^ Michael Brady (ed.). 2011 New Waves in Metaethics. Aldershot : Palgrave Macmillan.
  6. ^ Mackie, J. L. Ethics, Inventing right and wrong. 1977 Penguin
  7. The retrieval of ethics
    . Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  8. ^ Campbell, R. J. (2011). The concept of truth. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.
  9. ^ Smith, Holly(1991). "Deriving Morality From Rationality". In Peter Vallentyne (ed.), Contractarianism and Rational choice: Essays on David Gauthier's Morals by Agreement. Cambridge University Press.
  10. ^ Noddings, Nel, “Ethics from the Stand Point Of Women,” in Deborah L. Rhode, ed., Theoretical Perspectives on Sexual Difference (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990).
  11. ^ Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes' error: emotion, reason, and the human brain. New York: Putnam.
  12. ^ Edmund L. Gettier 1963. "Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?" From Analysis 23 ( 1963): 121-123.
  13. ^ Quine, W.V.O. (1951), "Two Dogmas of Empiricism," The Philosophical Review 60: 20-43. Reprinted in his 1953 From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press.
  14. ^ (Lyotard, Jean François, 1979, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge
  15. ^ Dancy, Stephen 2004 Ethics Without Principles. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  16. .
  17. .
  18. ^ Miller, C. (2009). "The Conditions of Moral Realism." The Journal of Philosophical Research, 34, 123-155.
  19. ^ FitzPatrick, William J Recent work on ethical realism Analysis.2009; 69: 746-760
  20. ^ Joyce, Richard and Kirchin, Simon (Eds.) A World without Values: Essays on John Mackie's Moral Error Theory Springer 2010
  21. ^ Moral Relativism Gilbert Harman Princeton University December 17, 2011, unpublished
  22. ^ Moral Relativism
  23. ^ Darwall, Stephen et al.1997 Moral Discourse and Practice, Oxford, p 7