F. H. Bradley

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.

F. H. Bradley
epistemic coherentism[1]

Francis Herbert Bradley

philosopher. His most important work was Appearance and Reality (1893).[4]

Life

Bradley was born at

Anglican preacher, and Emma Linton, Charles's second wife. A. C. Bradley was his brother. Educated at Cheltenham College and Marlborough College, he read, as a teenager, some of Immanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. In 1865, he entered University College, Oxford. In 1870, he was elected to a fellowship at Oxford's Merton College where he remained until his death in 1924.[5]
Bradley is buried in Holywell Cemetery in Oxford.

During his life, Bradley was a respected philosopher and was granted honorary degrees many times. He was the first British philosopher to be awarded the

Hegelian philosopher, his own unique brand of philosophy was inspired by, and contained elements of, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
's dialectical method.

Philosophy

Bradley rejected the

Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling
, and Hegel, although Bradley tended to downplay his influences.

In 1909, Bradley published an essay entitled "On Truth and Coherence" in the journal Mind (reprinted in Essays on Truth and Reality). The essay criticises a form of infallibilist foundationalism in epistemology. The philosopher Robert Stern has argued that in this paper Bradley defends coherence not as an account of justification but as a criterion or test for truth.[6]

Bradley also defends a novel theory of

facts. For Bradley, facts can justify our beliefs, but no fact justifies any belief to the point where it is immune from revision. "And the view which I advocate takes them [facts] all as in principle fallible… Facts for it [his view] are true, we may say, just so far as they work, just so far as they contribute to the order of experience. … And there is no ‘fact’ which possesses an absolute right."[7] Facts of history are, for Bradley, arrived at via an inferential process. "The historical fact then (for us) is a conclusion; … For everything that we say we think we have reasons, our realities are built up of explicit or hidden inferences; in a single word, facts are inferential, and their actuality depends on the correctness of the reasoning which makes them what they are."[8]

Moral philosophy

Bradley's view of morality was driven by his criticism of the idea of self used in the current utilitarian theories of ethics.[9] He addressed the central question of "Why should I be moral?"[10]

He opposed individualism, instead defending the view of self and morality as essentially social. Bradley held that our moral duty was founded on the need to cultivate our ideal "good self" in opposition to our "bad self".[11] However, he acknowledged that society could not be the source of our moral life, of our quest to realise our ideal self. For example, some societies may need moral reform from within, and this reform is based on standards which must come from elsewhere than the standards of that society.[12]

He made the best of this admission in suggesting that the ideal self can be realised through following religion.[13]

His views of the social self in his moral theorising are relevant to the views of Fichte, George Herbert Mead, and pragmatism. They are also compatible with modern views such as those of Richard Rorty and anti-individualism approaches.[14]

Legacy

Bradley's philosophical reputation declined greatly after his death. British idealism was practically eliminated by

verification principle
; e.g., statements such as "The Absolute enters into, but is itself incapable of, evolution and progress." There has in recent years, however, been a resurgence of interest in Bradley's and other idealist philosophers' work in the Anglo-American academic community.[15]

In 1914, a then-unknown

First World War, Eliot was unable to return to Harvard for his oral defence, resulting in the university never conferring the degree. Nevertheless, Bradley remained an influence on Eliot's poetry.[16]

Books and publications

See also

References

  1. ^ a b Coherentism in Epistemology (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
  2. ^ Campbell, Charles Arthur (The Continuum Encyclopedia of British Philosophy)
  3. ^ James Ward (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
  4. .
  5. ^ Levens, R.G.C., ed. (1964). Merton College Register 1900–1964. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. p. 1.
  6. JSTOR 40040722
    .
  7. ^ Pg. 210. Bradley, F. H. Essay. “On Truth and Coherence,” in Essays on Truth and Reality. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962.
  8. ^ Pg. 90. The Presuppositions of Critical History by F. H. Bradley, ed. Rubinoff, Lionel. J. M. Dent & Sons (Canada) Limited. 1968.
  9. ^ preface, Ethical studies: selected essays, G Herbert Bradley Liberal Arts Press, 1951
  10. ^ Ethical studies: selected essays, G Herbert Bradley Liberal Arts Press, 1951 p6.
  11. ^ Ethical studies: selected essays, G Herbert Bradley Liberal Arts Press, 1951, p153
  12. ^ Francis Herbert Bradley (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
  13. ^ Ethical studies: selected essays, G Herbert Bradley Liberal Arts Press, 1951, final essay: Selfishness and self-sacrifice
  14. ^ Goldberg, Sanford (2007). Anti-individualism: mind and language, knowledge and justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  15. .
  16. ^ Kenner, Hugh (1959). Bradley. From The Invisible Poet. New York: Ivan Obolensky.

External links