Recklessness (law)
In criminal law and in the law of tort, recklessness may be defined as the state of mind where a person deliberately and unjustifiably pursues a course of action while consciously disregarding any risks flowing from such action.[a] Recklessness is less culpable than malice, but is more blameworthy than carelessness.
Mens rea and actus reus
To commit a criminal offence of ordinary liability (as opposed to
Criminal law recognizes recklessness as one of four main classes of mental state constituting mens rea elements to establish liability, namely:
- Intention: intending the action; foreseeing the result; desiring the result: e.g. murder.
- Knowledge: knowing of the falsity or wrongfulness of one's actions or knowledge of a risk that a prohibited result is likely to occur but proceeding anyway. This also includes wilful blindness in most jurisdictions, and recklessness in some others. An example would be offenses involving possession: the accused must have controlled the item and knew that it was contraband.
- Wilful blindness: having a subjective awareness that a risk could exist (but not necessarily full knowledge) but proceeding without making more inquiries, e.g. a person is asked to bring a suitcase across a border: the person may not know that the suitcase contains drugs but has some suspicions (the person may think the suitcase could contain large sums of money) and, without ever asking or checking what's inside, bringing the suitcase across the border.
- Recklessness: willingly taking an initial action that a reasonable person would know will likely lead to the actus reus being committed, e.g. drinking alcohol and then driving as a result of automation due to intoxication.
- Carelessness (also known as negligence): failing to exercise due diligence to prevent the actus reus that caused the harm from occurring – rarely used in criminal law, often encountered in regulatory offenses (e.g. careless driving) or in the civil law tort of negligence – these are known as strict liability offenses.
The tests for any mens rea element relies on an assessment of whether the accused had foresight of the prohibited consequences and desired to cause those consequences to occur. The three types of test are:
- subjective where the court attempts to establish what the accused was actually thinking at the time the actus reus was caused;
- objective where the court imputes mens rea elements on the basis that a reasonable person with the same general knowledge and abilities as the accused would have had those elements, (although R v Gemmell and Richards deprecated this in England and Wales);[1] or
- hybrid, i.e. the test is both subjective and objective
The most culpable mens rea elements will have both foresight and desire on a subjective basis.
A subjective test is applied to offenses requiring intent, knowledge or wilful blindness.
For recklessness, a subjective test is applied to determine whether accused wilfully took an initial action that is inherently risky (such as drinking alcohol) but an objective test is applied to determine whether the commission of the actus reus could be foreseen (by a reasonable person).
For carelessness, once the prosecution proved the acteus reus, the defendant must prove that they exercised all the care a reasonable person would to prevent the actus reus from occurring.
Recklessness shows less culpability than intention, but more culpability than criminal negligence.[2]
There are also absolute liability offenses such as speeding. These do not require a guilty mind and due diligence is not a defense but a person cannot be imprisoned for an absolute liability offense.
Recklessness usually arises when an accused should be aware of the potentially adverse consequences to the planned actions, but has gone ahead anyway, exposing a particular individual or unknown victim to the risk of suffering the foreseen harm but not actually desiring that the victim be hurt. The accused is a social danger because they gamble with the safety of others, and, unless they exercised all possible due diligence, the fact they might have acted to try to avoid the injury from occurring is relevant only to mitigate the sentence. Note that gross criminal negligence represents such a serious failure to foresee that in any other person, it would have been recklessness.
A statutorily defined offence will be presumed to require mens rea, even if the Act is silent on the issue.[3]
Criminal systems of the civil law tradition distinguish between intention in the broad sense (dolus directus and dolus eventualis), and negligence. Negligence does not carry criminal responsibility unless a particular crime provides for its punishment.[4][5]
United States
Black's Law Dictionary defines recklessness in American law as "Conduct whereby the actor does not desire harmful consequence but ... foresees the possibility and consciously takes the risk", or alternatively as "a state of mind in which a person does not care about the consequences of his or her actions".[6] In American courts, like English courts, a wrongdoer is found guilty of recklessness based upon the subjective test rule, where the accused must have had the same reasonable knowledge or ability to know the circumstances surrounding the incident in order to be found guilty of recklessness.
In American
England and Wales
The modern definition of recklessness has developed from
The Court of Criminal Appeal reversed the conviction by the trial judge because "maliciously" was read to mean that the result was a reasonably foreseeable consequence of the defendant's actions, saying:
In any statutory definition of a crime, malice must be taken ... as requiring either:
- an actual intention to do the particular kind of harm that in fact was done; or
- recklessness as to whether such harm should occur or not (i.e. the accused has foreseen that the particular kind of harm might be done and yet has gone on to take the risk of it).
This type of recklessness is called "Cunningham recklessness".[9]
The current test in England and Wales is thus one of subjective recklessness, as reaffirmed by the House of Lords in R v G [2003].[10]
R v Caldwell and R v Lawrence
In R v Caldwell [1982] AC 341 a new definition of recklessness was adopted.
In late 1979, Caldwell, a disgruntled former hotel employee who had recently been fired by his boss, got very drunk one night and decided to set fire to his former employer's hotel, intending to damage the property. When he set the blaze there were ten guests asleep inside the hotel, and though the fire was extinguished quickly, Caldwell was charged not only with
Caldwell was convicted under section 1(2), which requires that the defendant shall:
- intend to destroy or damage any property or be reckless as to [the same] and
- intend by the destruction or damage to endanger the life of another or be reckless as to whether the life of another would be thereby endangered.
The House of Lords was mainly concerned with the extent to which self-induced drunkenness could be a defence to offences of specific intent and basic intent, the latter encompassing recklessness. The Lords ultimately ruled that self-induced intoxication could be a defence to specific intent, but not to basic intent, i.e. recklessness.
The discussion of recklessness in this case tends to be largely
- he does an act which in fact creates an obvious risk that property will be destroyed or damaged; and
- when he does the act, he either has not given any thought to the possibility of there being any such risk or has recognised that there was some risk involved and has nonetheless gone on to do it.
To that extent, the test is one of obviousness, i.e. if it would have been obvious to the reasonable person, the defendant will be punished for failing to foresee it.
The decision in Caldwell was followed in R v Lawrence [1982] AC 510
Recklessness on the part of the doer of an act presupposes that there is something in the circumstances that would have drawn the attention of an ordinary prudent individual to the possibility that his act was capable of causing the kind of serious harmful consequences that the section that created the offence was intended to prevent, and that the risk of those harmful consequences occurring was not so slight that an ordinary prudent individual would feel justified in treating them as negligible. It is only when this is so that the doer of the act is acting "recklessly" if, before doing the act, he either fails to give any thought to the possibility of there being any such risk or, having recognised that there was such a risk, he nevertheless goes on to do it.
Archbold Criminal Pleading, Evidence and Practice, 1999, para 17–52 et seq., refers to this definition of recklessness as "Caldwell/Lawrence recklessness", and at para 17–57 as "Diplock recklessness" and at para 17–56 as the "Caldwell test".
This form of recklessness is also called "objective recklessness".[12]
In Elliot v C (a minor)[13] a 14-year-old schoolgirl of low intelligence, who was tired and hungry, inadvertently burned down a garden shed. It was accepted that she did not foresee the risk of fire, and that she had not considered the possible consequences of her action. The court reluctantly followed Caldwell. It held that a defendant is reckless as to whether property is destroyed if he or she fails to give any thought to the possibility that there is a risk that property will be destroyed that would be obvious to a reasonably prudent person, even though that risk would not have been obvious to the defendant (by reason of age or lack of experience or understanding) if he had given any thought to the possibility that there was risk that property would be destroyed.
The focus of this test is the nature of the defendant's conduct rather than his mental state and it became the subject of major criticism. For example, how was the direction to apply to the defendant who had considered the risk and only continued to act after deciding (wrongly as it would later appear) that no risk existed? See Chief Constable of Avon and Somerset v Shimmen 84 Cr App R 7, [1986] Crim LR 800, DC and R v Merrick [1996] 1 Cr App R 130, CA.
In the continuing judicial debate, Lord Keith observed in R v Reid (1992) 3 AER 673 (a reckless driving case) that an absence of something from a person's state of mind is as much part of their state of mind as is its presence. Inadvertence to risk is no less a subjective state of mind than is disregard of a recognised risk. Lord Keith stressed that Lord Diplock qualified the model direction as "an appropriate instruction" only, seeking to introduce different standards for different offences. It was further argued that the model direction breached Article 6 of the European Convention on Human Rights in cases involving a minor or other persons of reduced capacity. The requirement is that "everyone is entitled to a fair and public hearing". But to judge the moral and legal culpability of a child by reference to the understanding and life experience of an adult is irrational and, therefore, unfair. In effect, it imposes strict liability. However, Z and others v United Kingdom (2002) 34 EHRR characterises Article 6 as procedural rather than substantive.
Restriction of this test to criminal damage and reckless driving
This test was intended to be of general application. In R v Seymour (E),
However, the Court of Appeal acted so as to limit its application to offences involving criminal damage and reckless driving.
After a period of confusion, in R v Satnam and Kewal,[15] the Court of Appeal held that this test did not apply to the meaning of the word "reckless" in the definition of rape in section 1 of the Sexual Offences (Amendment) Act 1976. The definition in section 1 of the Sexual Offences Act 2003, which supersedes the 1976 Act in cases arising after 1 May 2004, replaced the test of recklessness as to consent with one of lack of reasonable belief in consent.
In R v Prentice and Sullman, R v Adomako, R v Holloway,
Abolition of reckless driving
The
R v Caldwell overruled
The decision in Caldwell was overruled by the House of Lords in the case of R v G, described below. The objective test that it introduced was phased out, and a form of subjective recklessness was introduced instead for cases involving criminal damage. The majority of mens rea of recklessness is now 'tested' using the Cunningham test.
R v G and another [2003] UKHL 50
Two boys, aged 11 and 12 years, were camping without their parents' permission when they entered the back yard of a shop in the early hours of the morning. Lighting some newspapers they found in the yard, they left, with the papers still burning. The newspapers set fire to nearby rubbish bins standing against the shop wall, where it spread up the wall and on to the roof of the shop. Approximately £1m damage was caused. The children argued they expected the fire to burn itself out and said they gave no thought to the risk of its spreading. When their appeal reached the House of Lords, Lord Bingham saw the need to modify Lord Diplock's definition to take account of the defence of
- a circumstance when he is aware of a risk that it exists or will exist;
- a result when he is aware of a risk that it will occur; and it is, in the circumstances known to him, unreasonable to take the risk.
He expressly brings the test back to a subjectivity in that an accused is to be judged on the basis of their age, experience and understanding rather than on the standard of a hypothetical reasonable person who might have better knowledge and understanding. Nevertheless, the test remains hybrid because the credibility of the accused's denial of knowledge and understanding will always be judged against an objective standard of what you would expect a person of the same general age and abilities as the accused to have known.
In Booth v Crown Prosecution Service (2006) All ER (D) 225 (Jan), the Divisional Court upheld a pedestrian's conviction on a charge under the
See also
- Recklessness (psychology)
- Willful blindness
- Willful violation
Notes
- ^ The precise definition of recklessness is a subject of debate.
References
- ^ R v Gemmell and Richards
- ^ Cases and Materials on Criminal Law - 10th ed. - Elliot & Wood
- ^ Sweet v Parsley
- ^ Dörmann, Doswald-Beck and Kolb, Elements of War Crimes, 491
- ^ Kaiser, Leistungsstörungen, 333
- ^ Black's Law Dictionary 1053 (Bryan A. Garner ed., 8th ed. abr. 2005).
- ^ "28 USC § 523(a)(6)". Retrieved July 2, 2012.
- ^ "Kawaauhau v. Geiger, 523 US 57 (1998)". Retrieved July 2, 2012.
- ^ Ormerod, David. Smith and Hogan's Criminal Law. Thirteenth Edition. Oxford University Press. 2011. Pages 118 and 119.
- ^ R v G [2003] 3 WLR 1060
- 974, [1981] RTR 217, [1981] Crim LR 409, HL, reversing 71 Cr App R 291
- ^ Ormerod, David. Smith and Hogan's Criminal Law. Oxford University Press. 13th ed. 2011. p. 121.
- ^ Elliot v C (a minor) (1983) 77 Cr App R 103, [1983] 1 WLR 939, [1983] 2 All ER 1055, [1983] Crim LR 616, DC
- ^ R v Seymour [1983] 2 AC 493, [1983] 3 WLR 349, [1983] 2 All ER 1058, 77 Cr App R 215, [1983] RTR 455, [1983] Crim LR 742, HL, affirming 76 Cr App R 211, CA
- ^ R v Satnam and Kewal (1985) 78 Cr App R 149, [1985] Crim LR 236, CA
- ^ R v Prentice and Sullman, R v Adomako, R v Holloway, [1994] QB 302, [1993] 3 WLR 927, 98 Cr App R 262, [1993] 4 All ER 877, [1994] Crim LR 598, CA
- ^ R v Adomako [1995] 1 AC 171, [1994] 3 WLR 288, [1994] 3 All ER 79, 99 Cr App R 362, HL, affirming the last mentioned decision
Bibliography
- Davies, Mitchell, Tales from the (Thames) River Bank: R v G and Another (2004) Jo, of Criminal Law.
- De Lia, Andrea, I confini tra recklessness e (criminal) negligence nel sistema penale statunitense, in Archivio Penale, 2024, 2, 1 ss.
- Dörmann, Knut; Doswald-Beck, Louise; Kolb, Robert (2003). "Appendix". Elements of War Crimes. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-81852-4.
- Elliott, D. W. Endangering Life by Destroying or Damaging Property (1997) CLR 382.
- Field, Stewart & Lynn, Mervyn, The Capacity for Recklessness (1992) 12 Legal Studies 74.
- Field, Stewart & Lynn, Mervyn, Capacity, Recklessness and the House of Lords (1993) CLR 127.
- Kaiser, Dagmar (2005). "Leistungsstōrungen". In Staudinger, Julius von; Martinek, Michael; Beckmann, Roland Michael (eds.). Eckpfeiler Des Zivilrechts. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 3-8059-1019-3.
- Leigh Recklessness After Reid (1993) 56 MLR 208.
- Stark, Findlay, Culpable carelessness: recklessness and negligence in criminal law, Cambridge, 2018, ISBN 978-1108465120.
- Williams, Glanville, Recklessness Redefined (1981) CLJ 252