Conjectural history

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.

Conjectural history is a type of

The Natural History of Religion. It was related to "philosophical history", a broader-based kind of historical theorising, but concentrated on the early history of man in a type of rational reconstruction that had little contact with evidence.[1][2][3]

Such conjectural history was the antithesis of the

humankind, even at the cost of detailed documentation.[4] It was not concerned with the political narrative and public life, but saw itself as an investigative "moral science".[5] General philosophical history was somewhat closer to narrative history than conjectural history could be, with its reliance in part on tenuous arguments on the nature of feudalism and early ethnographical reports from European travellers.[6] For Stewart the Dissertation on the Origin of Languages by Adam Smith was an important example.[7] To justify the procedures of conjectural history, there needed to be an assumption of the uniformity of human nature, or as Stewart put it, the "capacities of the human mind".[8]

Conjectural history has been identified as "the core of a theory" of

Early Modern context

There was nothing new in the idea of stages of society on its own, but social thinking itself was changing in

Early Modern Europe, particularly on civil society in its components, civility
and "society".

Models and the "savage"

Hodgen comments, in a chapter From Hierarchy to History, on the widespread use of "conjectural series" for historical explanation in the Early Modern period. The great chain of being was a static idea. "Stage series" had roots in classical thought, but might be associated with cyclic models, or incorporate ideas of decline with those of progress. She writes that in time

... it seems certain that hierarchical ideas, temporalized to suit the needs of the conjectural historian of culture, were mixed with historical assumptions concerning the savage as a conjectural first member of these conjectural series.[13]

Early Modern natural history

While the

Baconian natural history, i.e. a systematic collection of observable information on natural phenomena. A natural history did not belong to natural philosophy, which was theoretical.[14]

Histoire raisonnée

The histoire raisonnée was a genre of historical writing developed in France in the 17th century, with concerns for the individual in social context, and the description of culture and customs as integral to history. It grew out of humanist historiography with its close relationship to classical Roman and Greek models, but brought to the surface social matters, in particular as they could explain the motivations of individuals. With Géraud de Cordemoy there came an interest in causality as playing a part in historical movement, as distinct from the humanist acceptance of personal fates being subject to Fortune.[15]

Stadial history

Contemporary terminology is stadial history, or in other words the discussion of stages of society by theoretical means (see

Some basic conjectural history on

Count Buffon debated the rise of civilization. The Scottish contribution then took the theory to a new level, with its anthropocentrism and detailed explanations of human manipulation of nature.[18] It laid emphasis on a typical society at its beginnings, regarding evidence from contemporary reports (particularly of Native Americans) as valid.[19]

Conjectural histories of language and writing

Adam Smith in lectures on rhetoric, given from 1748,[20] advanced a speculative history of language; he wrote that he had been prompted by a 1747 work of Gabriel Girard. He was then interested in our awareness of literary style.[21] This is the example that Dugald Stewart took up in coining the phrase "conjectural history". Elements would have been recognised at the time as drawing on the Bible, and in classical literature Lucretius; it is now considered Smith was influenced by Montesquieu on law and government. The theory on language and its typology over time has been seen as typical of Smith's historical approach; and even the foundation of his later well-known work on political economy. Caveats have also been entered, by David Raphael: it cannot be stretched to Smith's history of astronomy; and the term can be seen as a misnomer.[22][23]

Monboddo, on the other hand, wrote at length a conjectural history of language because he emphasised the history of

Divine Legation of Moses, a work supporting biblical authority, around 1740. It was taken up in France after the translation in Essai sur les hiéroglyphes des Égyptiens. Where writing moved from pictograms to alphabets, he saw language use as having moved analogously from gestures to forms and figures of speech.[25]

The four stages theory

The term "conjectural history" was not generally accepted in Stewart's time.[26] There was an orthodox four stages theory of society, the stages being:

  1. hunting;
  2. pasturage
    ;
  3. agriculture; and
  4. commerce.

This ladder-like ordering was taken to be a strict, linear progression, or unilineal evolution. Some economic determinism applied, in the sense that the baseline of subsistence was assumed to have a serious effect on social matters. The stages were supposed to represent progress on a moral level, as well as that of economic complexity. French as well as Scottish Enlightenment writers subscribed to such a pattern.[27]

The invention of this type of theory (three or four stages) is attributed to a number of European writers from the 1750s onwards, such as Adam Smith,

natural progress of opulence" is a closely related theory.[30]

Representative works

Besides Adam Smith, prominent Scottish authors in the field of conjectural history included

feral children as material.[33] Robertson in his History of America moves between narrative and conjectural history.[34]

Adam Ferguson, An Essay on the History of Civil Society (1767)

Ferguson in this work attempted a rigorous identification of the hunter stage with the so-called

foundation story in the style of classical history, proposing instead that unintended consequences could have more to do with the "establishment" of a society than a self-conscious law-giver.[36]

John Millar, Observations concerning the Distinction of Ranks in Society (1771)

Millar argued in terms of a "system of manners" associated with each of the four stages.[37] He also discussed the advance of freedom, and denounced slavery.[38] As property became more complex, it followed that government did so also.[39] Poovey states that this work makes apparent the relationship of conjectural history with the experimental moral philosophy of Thomas Reid and George Turnbull.[40]

Lord Kames, Sketches of the History of Man (1774)

Kames has been called the leader of Scottish conjectural history, and had objections he expressed in correspondence to both Rousseau and the approach of Montesquieu, as reducing the role of human nature, which he thought was not a constant but the goal of the investigation.[11] The connection was that conjectural history was to be used as a framework of a discussion of natural law.[26] In writing to Basel in search of a suitable opponent to Rousseau, Kames prompted a work from Isaak Iselin, Ueber die Geschichte der Menschheit (1764), which is also a conjectural history.[11][41]

The Sketches was a collection of essays on social, cultural and political topics.

providential order allows the historian to write in the absence of a full factual basis.[48] A German translation by Anton Ernst Klausing appeared as Versuche über die Geschichte des Menschen from 1774.[49]

Later developments

The tradition comes to an end

Mainstream conjectural and philosophical history, in the Scottish style, hardly survived as a living tradition into the 1790s. Works went out of print; younger authors such as

John Adams, William Alexander and John Logan failed to renew the ideas, with Alexander's History of Women (1779) being criticised as shallow.[50][51] Dugald Stewart's formulation of conjectural history was published in 1794, in his Account of Adam Smith for the Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh.[52] The question has been raised as to Stewart's intention then in describing the tradition in that way, and John Burrow has argued that he wished to dissociate Smith from political radicalism.[53]

Where stadial theory appeared in later authors, the original thrust was distorted.[50] Hopfl has said that the heirs were James Mill, John Stuart Mill, and Auguste Comte.[54] Hawthorne writes instead of the historical/sociological insights of the Scots being lost in the British context, despite the "tension between a 'natural' account of civil society and a developing sense of the factual importance and moral difficulties of individualism" having become apparent, to utilitarianism and vaguer evolutionism.[55]

Religious opposition

The Encyclopædia Britannica, in its

scriptural monogenism.[57]

Relationship to antiquarianism

Conjectural argument had a bad name in 18th century British

feudal system was a topic of considerable antiquarian interest.[59] The stadial history was embraced by Thomas Pownall.[58]

Conjectural history of peoples

Lewis Henry Morgan. Eventually, in the 20th century, field work and structural functionalism led to a rejection of the whole paradigm.[61]

"Scottish orientalism"

References

  • Margaret T. Hodgen (1971). Early Anthropology in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries. University of Pennsylvania Press. .
  • H. M. Hopfl, From Savage to Scotsman: Conjectural History in the Scottish Enlightenment, Journal of British Studies Vol. 17, No. 2 (Spring, 1978), pp. 19–40. Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of The North American Conference on British Studies. Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/175389
  • Phyllis K. Leffler, The "Histoire Raisonnee," 1660–1720: A Pre-Enlightenment Genre, Journal of the History of Ideas Vol. 37, No. 2 (Apr. - Jun., 1976), pp. 219–240. Published by: University of Pennsylvania Press. Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2708822
  • Robert Nisbet and Gustavo Costa, Vico and the Idea of Progress, Social Research Vol. 43, No. 3, Vico and Contemporary Thought—1 (Autumn 1976), pp. 625–639. Published by: The New School. Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/40970245
  • .
  • Rosemary Sweet (2004). Antiquaries: The Discovery of the Part in Eighteenth-Century Britain. Hambledon & London. .

Notes

  1. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  2. . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  3. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  4. ^ Nisbet and Costa, p. 629.
  5. . Retrieved 3 March 2013.
  6. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  7. ^ Broadie, Alexander. "Scottish Philosophy in the 18th Century". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  8. .
  9. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  10. ^ Pocock, p. 305.
  11. ^ . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  12. . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  13. ^ Hodgen, p. 467.
  14. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  15. ^ Leffler, pp. 223–9.
  16. ^ . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  17. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  18. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  19. ^ Hopfl, pp. 24–5.
  20. .
  21. .
  22. .
  23. .
  24. .
  25. .
  26. ^ . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  27. . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  28. . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  29. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  30. . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  31. .
  32. . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  33. . Retrieved 1 March 2013.
  34. ^ Hopfl, p. 21.
  35. ^ Pocock, pp. 330–5.
  36. ^ Hopfl, p. 30.
  37. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  38. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  39. .
  40. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  41. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  42. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  43. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  44. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  45. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  46. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  47. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  48. . Retrieved 2 March 2013.
  49. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  50. ^ . Retrieved 3 March 2013.
  51. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  52. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  53. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  54. ^ Hopfl, p. 32.
  55. .
  56. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  57. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  58. ^ a b Sweet, pp. 20–3.
  59. . Retrieved 3 March 2013.
  60. . Retrieved 4 March 2013.
  61. . Retrieved 5 March 2013.