Effective altruism: Difference between revisions

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.
Content deleted Content added
Extended confirmed users
736 edits
Extended confirmed users
15,438 edits
partially reverted changes to lead paragraph: "to improve the quality of life [of] others" is not what the sources say (and indeed, sometimes the goal is first of all to benefit others by keeping them alive, to say nothing of quality of life); and I don't think it's helpful to readers to put Altruism and Effectiveness in a hatnote; if the terms are important (and I think they are, but this could be argued further on the talk page) then their meaning should be in the text
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Philosophy and practice of using evidence to determine the most effective ways to benefit others}}
{{Short description|Philosophy and practice of using evidence to determine the most effective ways to benefit others}}
{{See also|Altruism|Effectiveness}}

[[File:London Thinks - Prof Peter Singer - What's the most good you can do.webm|thumb|Philosopher [[Peter Singer]] lectures on 'What's [[The Most Good You Can Do|the most good you can do]]?' at [[Conway Hall]] in 2015.]]
[[File:London Thinks - Prof Peter Singer - What's the most good you can do.webm|thumb|Philosopher [[Peter Singer]] lectures on 'What's [[The Most Good You Can Do|the most good you can do]]?' at [[Conway Hall]] in 2015.]]
'''Effective altruism''' is a [[Philosophical movement|philosophical]] and [[social movement]] that advocates the use of [[Scientific evidence|evidence]] and [[reasoning]] to determine the most effective ways to improve the quality of life others.<ref name="MacAskill-intro">{{cite journal|last=MacAskill|first=William|author-link=William MacAskill|title=Effective altruism: introduction|journal=Essays in Philosophy|date=January 2017|volume=18|issue=1|page=eP1580:1–5|doi=10.7710/1526-0569.1580|language=en|issn=1526-0569|url=https://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/vol18/iss1/1|access-date=2020-02-08|archive-date=2019-08-07|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190807105816/https://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/vol18/iss1/1/|url-status=live}}</ref>{{rp|2}}<ref name="Singer2015">{{cite book |last=Singer |first=Peter |author-link=Peter Singer |date=2015 |title=[[The Most Good You Can Do|The Most Good You Can Do: How Effective Altruism Is Changing Ideas About Living Ethically]] |series=Castle lectures in ethics, politics, and economics |location=New Haven |publisher=[[Yale University Press]] |isbn=9780300180275 |oclc=890614537 }}</ref>{{rp|4–7}} Such improvement is commonly measured in [[Quality-adjusted life year|Quality-adjusted life years]].<ref name="doing-good-better">{{cite book |last=MacAskill |first=William |author-link=William MacAskill |title=[[Doing Good Better|Doing Good Better: How Effective Altruism Can Help You Help Others, Do Work that Matters, and Make Smarter Choices about Giving Back]] |date=2016 |orig-year=2015 |location=New York |publisher=Avery |isbn=9781592409662 |oclc=932001639 }}</ref>
'''Effective altruism''' is a [[Philosophical movement|philosophical]] and [[social movement]] that advocates the use of [[Scientific evidence|evidence]] and [[reasoning]] to determine the most effective ways to benefit others.<ref name="MacAskill-intro">{{cite journal|last=MacAskill|first=William|author-link=William MacAskill|title=Effective altruism: introduction|journal=Essays in Philosophy|date=January 2017|volume=18|issue=1|page=eP1580:1–5|doi=10.7710/1526-0569.1580|language=en|issn=1526-0569|url=https://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/vol18/iss1/1|access-date=2020-02-08|archive-date=2019-08-07|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190807105816/https://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/vol18/iss1/1/|url-status=live}}</ref>{{rp|2}}<ref name="Singer2015">{{cite book |last=Singer |first=Peter |author-link=Peter Singer |date=2015 |title=[[The Most Good You Can Do|The Most Good You Can Do: How Effective Altruism Is Changing Ideas About Living Ethically]] |series=Castle lectures in ethics, politics, and economics |location=New Haven |publisher=[[Yale University Press]] |isbn=9780300180275 |oclc=890614537 }}</ref>{{rp|4–7}} ''[[Altruism]]'' refers to improving the lives of others, as opposed to [[egoism]], which emphasizes only self-interest.<ref name="Singer2015"/>{{rp|4–5}}<ref name="doing-good-better">{{cite book |last=MacAskill |first=William |author-link=William MacAskill |title=[[Doing Good Better|Doing Good Better: How Effective Altruism Can Help You Help Others, Do Work that Matters, and Make Smarter Choices about Giving Back]] |date=2016 |orig-year=2015 |location=New York |publisher=Avery |isbn=9781592409662 |oclc=932001639 }}</ref>{{rp|12}} ''[[Effectiveness]]'' refers to doing the ''most'' good with whatever resources are available, as opposed to doing only ''some'' amount of good. This is achieved by using evidence and reasoning to identify which actions do the most good, as opposed to acting instinctively or intuitively.<ref name="Singer2015"/>{{rp|6–7}}<ref name="doing-good-better"/>{{rp|12}} For health benefits, such improvement is commonly measured in [[quality-adjusted life year]]s.<ref name="doing-good-better"/>{{rp|34}}


People who embrace effective altruism are labeled ''effective altruists''.<ref>The term ''effective altruists'' is used to refer to people who embrace effective altruism in many published sources such as {{harvtxt|Oliver|2014}}, {{harvtxt|Singer|2015}}, and {{harvtxt|MacAskill|2017}}, though as {{harvtxt|Pummer|MacAskill|2020}} noted, calling people "effective altruists" just means minimally that they are engaged in the project of "using evidence and reason to try to find out how to do the most good, and on this basis trying to do the most good", not that they are perfectly effective nor even that they necessarily participate in the effective altruism community.</ref> While many effective altruists have focused on the [[non-profit sector]], the philosophy of effective altruism applies more broadly to the process of prioritizing the scientific projects, companies, and policy initiatives that can be estimated to save lives, help people, or otherwise have the biggest benefit.<ref name="doing-good-better"/>{{rp|179–195}} A related group that attracts some effective altruists is the [[LessWrong#Effective altruism|rationalist community]].<ref name=chiversEA>{{Cite book|last=Chivers|first=Tom|title=The AI Does Not Hate You|publisher=Weidenfeld & Nicolson|year=2019|isbn=978-1474608770|chapter=Chapter 38: The Effective Altruists}}</ref>
People who embrace effective altruism are labeled ''effective altruists''.<ref>The term ''effective altruists'' is used to refer to people who embrace effective altruism in many published sources such as {{harvtxt|Oliver|2014}}, {{harvtxt|Singer|2015}}, and {{harvtxt|MacAskill|2017}}, though as {{harvtxt|Pummer|MacAskill|2020}} noted, calling people "effective altruists" just means minimally that they are engaged in the project of "using evidence and reason to try to find out how to do the most good, and on this basis trying to do the most good", not that they are perfectly effective nor even that they necessarily participate in the effective altruism community.</ref> While many effective altruists have focused on the [[non-profit sector]], the philosophy of effective altruism applies more broadly to the process of prioritizing the scientific projects, companies, and policy initiatives that can be estimated to save lives, help people, or otherwise have the biggest benefit.<ref name="doing-good-better"/>{{rp|179–195}} A related group that attracts some effective altruists is the [[LessWrong#Effective altruism|rationalist community]].<ref name=chiversEA>{{Cite book|last=Chivers|first=Tom|title=The AI Does Not Hate You|publisher=Weidenfeld & Nicolson|year=2019|isbn=978-1474608770|chapter=Chapter 38: The Effective Altruists}}</ref>

Revision as of 17:18, 3 December 2021

Philosopher Peter Singer lectures on 'What's the most good you can do?' at Conway Hall in 2015.

Effective altruism is a

reasoning to determine the most effective ways to benefit others.[1]: 2 [2]: 4–7  Altruism refers to improving the lives of others, as opposed to egoism, which emphasizes only self-interest.[2]: 4–5 [3]: 12  Effectiveness refers to doing the most good with whatever resources are available, as opposed to doing only some amount of good. This is achieved by using evidence and reasoning to identify which actions do the most good, as opposed to acting instinctively or intuitively.[2]: 6–7 [3]: 12  For health benefits, such improvement is commonly measured in quality-adjusted life years.[3]
: 34 

People who embrace effective altruism are labeled effective altruists.

non-profit sector, the philosophy of effective altruism applies more broadly to the process of prioritizing the scientific projects, companies, and policy initiatives that can be estimated to save lives, help people, or otherwise have the biggest benefit.[3]: 179–195  A related group that attracts some effective altruists is the rationalist community.[5]

Philosophical principles of effective altruism include impartiality, cause neutrality, cost-effectiveness, and counterfactual reasoning. Common practices of effective altruists include significant charitable donation, sometimes through publicly pledging to donate a certain percentage of income, and basing career choices on the amount of good that the career achieves, which may include the strategy of earning to give. Many effective altruists have prioritized taking action to address global poverty, animal welfare, and risks to the survival and flourishing of humanity and its descendants over the long-term future.

Various critics of effective altruism have objected to the practice of cause prioritization and to what they perceive as bias toward measurable interventions as well as neglect of more radical economic changes.

Philosophy

Peter Singer is one of several philosophers who helped popularize effective altruism.

Philosophers play an important role in effective altruism. Much of the published literature on the subject poses philosophical questions about why and how to use evidence and reasoning to determine the most effective ways to benefit others. It then tries to figure out the most plausible answers to those questions, so that people can act on the basis of those answers.[6][7] Such philosophical questions shift the starting point of reasoning from "what to do" to why and how to do it.[8]

The "guiding question"[3]: 14  of effective altruism is: how can we, individually and collectively, do the most good?[2]: 5 [6] Subsequent questions include:

  • "What counts as 'the most good'?"[2]: 7 
  • "How can I do the most good, given what others are likely to do?"[6]
  • "Does everyone's suffering count equally?"[2]: 7 
  • "Does 'the most good you can do' mean that it is wrong to give priority to one's own children?"[2]: 8 
  • "What about other values, like justice, freedom, equality, and knowledge?"[2]: 8 
  • "Can everyone practice effective altruism?"[2]: 9 
  • Is it better to think of effective altruism "as an 'opportunity' or an 'obligation'"?[7]: 16 
  • "What if one's act reduces suffering, but to do so one must lie or harm an innocent person?"
    the ends justify the means"?[7]
    : 20 
  • "What would have happened otherwise?"[3]: 13 
  • "What are the chances of success, and how good would success be?"[3]: 13 

Effective altruists have yet to reach consensus on the answers to such questions.

meta-ethics.[1][6] For example, the moral theory of consequentialism, including utilitarianism, supports the aim of using resources to benefit others as much as possible. However, effective altruism is not the same as consequentialism.[1][6]

Views vary about whether effective altruism entails

deontological ethics, virtue ethics, as well as many traditional religious teachings on altruism, can all be compatible with the project of effective altruism.[1][6] Effective altruism is not a complete philosophy of how to live morally, but effective altruism may be relevant for any view that assumes some reason to promote the good and that assumes that the well-being of others is part of the good.[7]
: 19 

Effective altruists such as Kelsey Piper reported that the questions posed by effective altruism have helped them learn more about complex problems as well as gain a deeper sense of meaning and a feeling of satisfaction from helping others more effectively.[11]

The following subsections describe important ideas that are discussed in the published literature about effective altruism.

Impartiality

An allegorical image of equality by Jean-Guillaume Moitte, 1793

Altruism, or benefitting others, can be driven by various motivations and justifications, including impartial or impersonal reasoning and sentiments such as sympathy and compassion.[12] Much of the published literature on effective altruism emphasizes impartial or impersonal reasoning and concludes that, other things being equal, everyone's well-being (and suffering) counts equally, without regard to individual identities.[2]: 85–95 [6][7]: 17–19  For example, philosopher Peter Singer, in his 1972 essay "Famine, Affluence, and Morality", wrote:[13]: 231–232, 237 

It makes no moral difference whether the person I can help is a neighbor's child ten yards away from me or a Bengali whose name I shall never know, ten thousand miles away. ... The moral point of view requires us to look beyond the interests of our own society. Previously, ... this may hardly have been feasible, but it is quite feasible now. From the moral point of view, the prevention of the starvation of millions of people outside our society must be considered at least as pressing as the upholding of property norms within our society.

This view has been influential among effective altruists.[14] Singer's arguments for impartiality were later repeated in other books by Singer[2][15] and expanded in the 1996 book Living High and Letting Die by philosopher Peter Unger.[16]

Impartiality about benefitting others combined with seeking to do the most good is compatible with prioritizing benefits to those who are in a worse state, because anyone who happens to be worse off will benefit more from an improvement in their state, all other things being equal (see § Global poverty alleviation below).[6]

Impartiality is also the basis of what is called the cause neutrality of effective altruism (see § Cause prioritization below): choosing among possible altruistic activities or causes (problems) based on whether they will do the most good with limited resources—as opposed to choosing among them based on other factors such as personal connections.[6]

Some effective altruists have argued that because the total sum of members of future generations will be larger than the current population, the way to do the most good is to focus on promoting long-term well-being by, for example, reducing

existential risks to humanity (see § Long-term future and global catastrophic risks below).[2]: 165–178 [17][18]

Some effective altruists think that the

Obstacles to impartiality

Singer speculated in "Famine, Affluence, and Morality" that whether people think and act impartially is likely to be affected by social influence: "What it is possible for a man to do and what he is likely to do are both, I think, very greatly influenced by what people around him are doing and expecting him to do."[13]: 237  In his 2015 book The Most Good You Can Do, Singer admitted that even though he had argued in 1972 that "we ought to give large proportions of our income to disaster relief funds", he did not do it himself: "even though I argued that this is what we ought to do, I did not do it myself".[2]: 13  He noted the role of social influence and psychological inertia as obstacles to acting altruistically.[2]: 13–14  Sociological research has shown that social influence can undermine altruistic activity.[22] To support people's ability to act altruistically on the basis of impartial reasoning, the effective altruism movement promotes additional values and actions that are not part of the minimal philosophical core of effective altruism, such as a collaborative spirit, honesty, transparency, and publicly pledging to donate a certain percentage of income or other resources.[1]: 2 

Cause prioritization

Many nonprofits emphasize effectiveness and evidence, but this is usually done with a single cause (problem) in mind, such as education or climate change.[23] Effective altruists, however, seek to compare the relative importance of different causes and allocate resources among them objectively, adopting cause neutrality.[24] One approach to cause neutrality, for example, is to choose the highest priority causes based on whether activities in each cause area efficiently advance broad goals, such as increasing human or animal welfare, and then focus attention on interventions in those cause areas.[25]

The information required for cause prioritization may involve collecting and processing complex

Cost-effectiveness

Effective altruist organizations have argued that some charities are far more effective than others, either because some do not achieve their goals or because of the varying cost of achieving those goals.[29][30] When possible, they seek to identify charities that are highly cost-effective, meaning that they achieve a large benefit for a given amount of money.[31] For example, they select health interventions on the basis of their impact as measured by lives extended per dollar, quality-adjusted life years (QALY) added per dollar, or disability-adjusted life years (DALY) reduced per dollar. This measure of disease burden is expressed as the number of years lost due to ill-health, disability, or early death.

Some effective altruism organizations prefer randomized controlled trials as a primary form of evidence,[31][32] as they are often considered to be at the highest level of evidence, e.g., in healthcare research.[33] Others have argued that requiring this stringent level of evidence unnecessarily narrows the focus to only those issues on which this kind of evidence can be developed, and that the history of philanthropy suggests that many effective interventions have proceeded without this level of evidence.[34]

Room for more funding

Effective altruist organizations consider the expected impact of a funding increase rather than evaluating the average value of all donations to the charity.[35][36] Effective altruists would avoid donating to organizations that lack "room" for more funding – those that face bottlenecks other than money that would prevent them from effectively employing additional resources.[37] For example, a medical charity might not be able to hire enough doctors or nurses to distribute the medical supplies it is capable of purchasing, or it might already be serving all of the potential patients in its market.

Counterfactual reasoning

Effective altruists have argued that counterfactual reasoning is important to determine which course of action maximizes positive impact. Many people assume that the best way to help people is through direct methods, such as working for a charity or providing social services,[38] but since charities and social-service providers can usually find people willing to work for them, effective altruists would compare the amount of good somebody does in a conventional altruistic career to how much good would have been done had the next-best candidate done the work instead. According to this reasoning, the marginal impact of a career is likely to be smaller than the gross impact.[39][40]

Behavior

The philosophical or intellectual part of effective altruism, described above, is about learning how to do the most good through the use of evidence and reasoning. The behavioral or practical part is about using what has been learned.[6][7]: 14 

Donation

Effective altruism encourages significant charitable donation. Some believe it is a moral duty to alleviate suffering through donations if the other uses of those funds do not offer comparable benefits to oneself,[13] leading some of them to lead a frugal lifestyle in order to give more.[41]

Giving What We Can (GWWC) is an organization whose members have pledged to donate at least 10% of their income for the remainder of their working lives to the causes that they believe are the most effective. GWWC was founded in 2009 by Toby Ord, a moral philosopher, who lives on £18,000 ($27,000) per year and donates the balance of his income.[42]

The Founders Pledge is a similar initiative run by the nonprofit Founders Forum for Good where startup founders make a legally binding commitment to donate at least 2% of their personal proceeds to charity in the event that they sell their business.[43][44] By January 2019, three years after launch, more than 1400 entrepreneurs had pledged an estimated $700 million and at least $91 million had been donated.[45]

Career choice

Effective altruists have argued that one's career is an important determinant of the amount of good one does,[46] both directly (through the services one provides) and indirectly (through one's consumption/investment/donation decisions).[47]

80,000 Hours is an organization that conducts research on which careers have the largest positive social impact and provides career advice based on that research.[48][49] It considers both direct and indirect kinds of altruistic employment.[50][51]

Earning to give has been proposed as a possible strategy for effective altruists. This strategy involves choosing to work in high-paying careers with the explicit goal of donating large sums of money to charity.[52][53] William MacAskill argued in 2014 that sufficient donations might justify an otherwise morally controversial career, since the marginal impact of taking an unethical job is small if someone else would have taken it regardless, while the impact of the donations could be large.[47] In 2017, 80,000 Hours recommended that it is better to avoid careers that do significant direct harm, even if it seems like the negative consequences could be outweighed by donations. This is because the harms from such careers may be hidden or otherwise hard to measure, and because they think it is important to account for moral uncertainty—for example, not knowing to what degree one should minimize the negative consequences that one hopes to outweigh by donations.[54]

Pundit

David Brooks criticized earning to give. He wrote that most people who work in finance and other high-paying industries value money for selfish reasons and that working among such people will cause effective altruists to become less altruistic.[55] Peter Singer responded to these criticisms in his book The Most Good You Can Do by giving examples of people who have been earning to give for years without losing their altruism.[56] Pascal-Emmanuel Gobry argued that the practice was "unsettling", explaining that "the implication seems to be that taking a high-paying job selling fraudulent mortgage-backed securities is more praiseworthy than taking a low-paying job at the local homeless shelter, so long as one buys enough anti-malarial bed nets".[57] Singer responded to this kind of "ethical objection" by arguing that effective altruists who are not utilitarians may be able to find a high-paying job that is not complicit in causing such harm, but even those who take such a complicit job have at least several ways of dealing with the situation, such as by lobbying the organization to change its harmful practices, which may be easier to do from their position inside the organization, or by quitting and blowing the whistle on the organization, which might not have been possible without gaining information while on the job.[2]
: 50–54 

Cause priorities

Since effective altruism aims for cause neutrality (see

factory farming, or averting nuclear warfare.[6] Many people in the effective altruist movement have prioritized global poverty, animal welfare, and risks to the survival and flourishing of humanity and its descendants over the long-term future.[59][32][27][60]

Global poverty alleviation

Global

poverty alleviation
has been a focus of some of the earliest and most prominent organizations associated with effective altruism.

Charity evaluator

Deworm the World Initiative, and GiveDirectly for direct unconditional cash transfers).[64][65]

The effective altruism organization The Life You Can Save, which originated from Singer's book with the same name,[15] works to alleviate global poverty by promoting evidence-backed charities, conducting philanthropy education, and changing the culture of giving in affluent countries.[66][67]

While much of the initial focus of effective altruism was on direct strategies such as health interventions and cash transfers, more systematic social, economic, and political reforms that would facilitate larger long-term poverty reduction have also attracted attention.

Open Philanthropy Project, for research and philanthropic funding of more speculative and diverse causes such as policy reform, global catastrophic risk reduction and scientific research.[69][70] It is a collaboration between GiveWell and Good Ventures.[71][72][73]

Animal welfare

Many effective altruists believe that cost-effective ways are available to reduce

animal suffering.[74][75][76] In 2010, Singer quoted estimates by the Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations and the British organization Fishcount that 60 billion land animals are slaughtered and between 1 and 2.7 trillion individual fish are killed each year for human consumption.[77][78][79] Singer argued that effective animal welfare altruists should prioritize changes to factory farming over pet welfare.[80][21] Singer also argued that, if animals such as chickens are assigned even a modicum of consciousness, total suffering can be reduced more effectively by reducing factory farming (for example, by reducing global meat consumption) than by reducing human poverty.[2]: 138, 146–147  Alternatively, Animal Ethics and Wild Animal Initiative focus on wild animal suffering.[81][82] In 2018, the book The End of Animal Farming by Jacy Reese Anthis discussed animal welfare issues from an effective altruism perspective, with a specific focus on the potential for cultured meat to address farm animal suffering and the importance of expanding the circle of concern to help people care more about future beings, wild animals, invertebrates, and artificial sentience.[83]

Animal Charity Evaluators (ACE) is an effective altruism organization that evaluates animal charities based on their cost-effectiveness and transparency, particularly those tackling factory farming.[84][85][2]: 139  Faunalytics is an organization loosely affiliated with the effective altruism community that focuses on animal welfare.[86][87] The Sentience Institute is an effective altruism think tank founded in 2017 to expand the moral circle to other species.[88][89]

Long-term future and global catastrophic risks

Focusing on the long-term future, some effective altruists believe that the total value of any meaningful metric (wealth, potential for suffering, potential for happiness, etc.) summed up over future generations, far exceeds the value for people living today.[59][17][90][91] Some researchers have found it psychologically difficult to contemplate the trade-off; Toby Ord stated, "Since there is so much work to be done to fix the needless suffering in our present, I was slow to turn to the future."[92]: 8  Reasons Ord gave for working on long-term issues include a belief that preventing long-term suffering is "even more neglected" than causes related to current suffering, and that the residents of the future are even more powerless to affect risks caused by current events than are current dispossessed populations".[92]: 8 

Philosophically, assessing the suffering of future populations involves multiple considerations. First, humanity (and other animals) may not exist at all, in which cases there is no suffering to alleviate (presuming that the process of eliminating the population does not itself involve suffering). Second, the cost of an incremental reduction in suffering in the future may be higher (e.g., because of increasing healthcare costs) or lower (brought down, e.g., by the ever-crashing cost of computing or renewable energy). Third, the value of a benefit or cost is affected by the time preferences of the recipient and the payer. Fourth, future suffering may be alleviated by current spending, potentially at a lower cost. Fifth, alleviating suffering sooner may have a knock-on effect of reducing/increasing future suffering. Sixth, if investing money produces outsized returns, that may provide the ability to reduce total suffering by more than if the money is instead donated before it can accumulate. Seventh, future populations may be so much wealthier than the current population that, even if a particular reduction in suffering costs more then than it does today, the population might still be better off by waiting.[93] Singer argued that existential risk should not be "the dominant public face of the effective altruism movement" because he claimed that doing so would drastically limit the movement's reach.[94]

In particular, the importance of addressing

advanced artificial intelligence is often highlighted and the subject of active research.[95] Because it is generally infeasible to use traditional research techniques such as randomized controlled trials to analyze existential risks, researchers such as Nick Bostrom have used methods such as expert opinion elicitation to estimate their importance.[96] Ord offered probability estimates for a number of existential risks in his 2020 book The Precipice.[97]

Organizations that work actively on research and advocacy for improving the long term future, and have connections with the effective altruism community, are the Future of Humanity Institute at the University of Oxford, the Centre for the Study of Existential Risk at the University of Cambridge, and the Future of Life Institute.[98] In addition, the Machine Intelligence Research Institute is focused on the more narrow mission of managing advanced artificial intelligence.[99][100]

History

The movement that later adopted the name effective altruism was created in the late 2000s as a community formed around

TED talk "The Why and How of Effective Altruism" in May 2013.[101] Other contributions were the writings of philosophers such as Singer on applied ethics and Bostrom on reducing the risk of human extinction, the founding of organizations such as GiveWell and The Life You Can Save, and the creation of internet forums such as LessWrong.[103]: 110 [104]

Effective altruism conferences (called Effective Altruism Global) have been held since 2013.[105][106] In 2015, Singer published The Most Good You Can Do.[80] In the same year MacAskill published Doing Good Better: How Effective Altruism Can Help You Make a Difference.[107][108][31]

In 2018, American news website Vox launched its Future Perfect section, led by journalist Dylan Matthews.[109] Future Perfect has published written pieces and podcasts on the mission of "Finding the best ways to do good",[110][111] including topics such as effective philanthropy,[112] high-impact career choice,[48] poverty reduction through women's empowerment,[113] improving children's learning efficiently through improving environmental health,[114] animal welfare improvements,[84] and ways to reduce global catastrophic risks.[115]

Key figures

Key figures in the effective altruism movement have included:

Criticism

Claims that comparisons within and across cause areas are illegitimate

Ken Berger and Robert Penna of Charity Navigator derided effective altruism as "defective altruism" and condemned its practice of "weighing causes and beneficiaries against one another", calling this "moralistic, in the worst sense of the word".[125]

Bias toward measurable interventions

Pascal-Emmanuel Gobry warns about the "measurement problem", stating that some areas, such as medical research, or helping to reform third-world governance "one grinding step at a time", are hard to measure with controlled cost-effectiveness experiments and therefore risk being undervalued by the effective altruism movement.[57] Jennifer Rubenstein also hypothesizes that effective altruism can be biased against difficult-to-measure causes.[104]

Perceived neglect of radical economic change

Mathew Snow argued that effective altruism "implores individuals to use their money to procure necessities for those who desperately need them, but says nothing about the system that determines how those necessities are produced and distributed in the first place".[126] Various critics have similarly objected to effective altruists' neglect of political causes such as anti-capitalism that change "the existing global institutional order".[127] Joshua Kissel replied that anti-capitalism is compatible with effective altruism in theory, while adding that effective altruists and anti-capitalists have reason to be more sympathetic to each other.[58] Brian Berkey argued that support for institutional change does not contradict the principles of effective altruism, because effective altruism is open to any action that will have the greatest positive impact on the world, including the possibility of changing the existing global institutional order.[127] Elizabeth Ashford argued that people are separately obligated to donate to effective aid charities and to reform the structures that are responsible for poverty.[128]

See also

Notes and references

  1. ^ from the original on 2019-08-07. Retrieved 2020-02-08.
  2. ^ .
  3. ^ .
  4. ^ The term effective altruists is used to refer to people who embrace effective altruism in many published sources such as Oliver (2014), Singer (2015), and MacAskill (2017), though as Pummer & MacAskill (2020) noted, calling people "effective altruists" just means minimally that they are engaged in the project of "using evidence and reason to try to find out how to do the most good, and on this basis trying to do the most good", not that they are perfectly effective nor even that they necessarily participate in the effective altruism community.
  5. .
  6. ^ .
  7. ^ .
  8. ^ a b c Crouch, Will (May 30, 2013). "What is effective altruism?". blog.practicalethics.ox.ac.uk. Practical Ethics blog, Philosophy Faculty, University of Oxford. Archived from the original on October 3, 2015. Retrieved February 4, 2020.
  9. ^ MacAskill (2019a) said of the emphasis on well-being in effective altruism: "This welfarism is 'tentative', however, insofar as it is taken to be merely a working assumption. The ultimate aim of the effective altruist project is to do as much good as possible; the current focus on wellbeing rests on the idea that, given the current state of the world and our incredible opportunity to benefit others, the best ways of promoting welfarist value are broadly the same as the best ways of promoting the good." (p. 18)
  10. ^ Singer (2015) expressed a clearly normative view: "Effective altruism is based on a very simple idea: we should do the most good we can. Obeying the usual rules about not stealing, cheating, hurting, and killing is not enough, or at least not enough for those of us who have the great good fortune to live in material comfort, who can feed, house, and clothe ourselves and our families and still have money or time to spare. Living a minimally acceptable ethical life involves using a substantial part of our spare resources to make the world a better place. Living a fully ethical life involves doing the most good we can." (p. vii)
  11. reported: "Second, effective altruism is a way of giving meaning to our own lives and finding fulfillment in what we do. Many effective altruists say that in doing good, they feel good. Effective altruists directly benefit others, but indirectly they often benefit themselves." (p. viii)
  12. ^ Kraut, Richard (August 25, 2016). "Altruism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.). See especially the section "4. Why care about others?" Archived 2020-01-26 at the Wayback Machine: "Radically different ways of answering these questions [about why to benefit others] can be found in moral philosophy."
  13. ^
    OCLC 907446001
    .
  14. ^ On the influence of Singer's essay "Famine, Affluence, and Morality" see, for example: Snow 2015, Singer 2015, pp. 13–20, and Lichtenberg, Judith (November 30, 2015). "Peter Singer's extremely altruistic heirs: Forty years after it was written, 'Famine, Affluence, and Morality' has spawned a radical new movement". The New Republic.
  15. ^
    OCLC 232980306
    .
  16. (PDF) from the original on 2020-06-07. Retrieved 2020-02-05.
  17. ^ a b Todd, Benjamin (October 24, 2017). "Introducing longtermism: How important are future generations?". 80000 Hours. Archived from the original on February 20, 2020. Retrieved February 8, 2020. Since the future is big, there could be far more people in the future than in the present generation. This means that if you want to help people in general, your key concern shouldn't be to help the present generation, but to ensure that the future goes well in the long-term. Previously, we called this the 'long-term value thesis', though it is now most commonly called 'longtermism'. This thesis is often confused with the claim that we shouldn't do anything to help people in the present generation. But the long-term value thesis is about what most matters—what we should do about it is a further question. It might turn out that the best way to help those in the future is to improve the lives of people in the present, such as through providing health and education.
  18. .
  19. from the original on 2019-08-07. Retrieved 2020-02-08.
  20. .
  21. ^ a b "Why Farmed Animals?". Animal Charity Evaluators. November 2016. Archived from the original on 2019-07-06. Retrieved 2018-12-09.
  22. . "More generally, laboratory studies of socially decontextualized groups show that person-level factors alone are generally unable to sustain cooperation at the high levels observed in many human groups. As noted above, these groups initially show much variation in contributions, with more altruistic individuals giving at high levels and more egoistic people contributing little or nothing at all. Contributions of more altruistic individuals then decline over time in response to their egoistic counterparts' noncooperation (Fehr & Gintis 2007, Sell & Wilson 1991). Thus, in the absence of social mechanisms—e.g., clear enforceable norms, opportunities to gain reputation or status for contributions to group efforts, or social connections between group members—contributions fall to very low levels." (p. 56)
  23. ^ Schambra, William A. (May 22, 2014). "Opinion: The coming showdown between philanthrolocalism and effective altruism". Philanthropy Daily. Archived from the original on February 5, 2020. Retrieved February 5, 2020. Strategic philanthropists like Paul Brest seek only to apply metrics to the selection of groups once a cause has been selected. But, altruist critics note, this foolishly leaves the choice of the cause itself willy-nilly to the all-too-often idiosyncratic, short-sighted, selfish impulses of the donor.
  24. ^ a b Schubert, Stefan (March 10, 2017). "Understanding cause-neutrality". Centre for Effective Altruism. Archived from the original on February 20, 2020. Retrieved March 10, 2020. Schubert said that the term cause neutrality has been used by various authors with different meanings and different decision rules.
  25. ^ Schubert (2017) called this approach the "cause-flexible investments" strategy and compared it to other strategies such as "cause-divergent investments". With regard to these two strategies, he noted: "How to prioritize between these two strategies is an important and understudied question."
  26. from the original on 2021-02-15. Retrieved 2020-09-19.
  27. ^ a b "Our current view of the world's most pressing problems". 80,000 Hours. Archived from the original on March 14, 2020. Retrieved March 10, 2020.
  28. ^ Karnofsky, Holden (January 26, 2018). "Update on cause prioritization at Open Philanthropy". www.openphilanthropy.org. Archived from the original on February 23, 2020. Retrieved March 10, 2020.
  29. ^ "Your dollar goes further when you fund the right program". GiveWell. Archived from the original on 2019-08-30. Retrieved 2013-03-10.
  30. ^ a b "Your Dollar Goes Further Overseas". GiveWell. Archived from the original on 2019-10-31. Retrieved 2013-03-10.
  31. ^ a b c d Thompson, Derek (June 15, 2015). "The Greatest Good". The Atlantic. Archived from the original on August 20, 2019. Retrieved March 6, 2017.
  32. ^ from the original on March 12, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  33. from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  34. ^ Karnofsky, Holden (April 4, 2016). "Hits-based giving". www.openphilanthropy.org. Archived from the original on July 16, 2019. Retrieved March 10, 2020.
  35. ^ Zhang, Linch (June 21, 2016). "How Can You do the Most Good with Your Charitable Giving? This Expert's Answers Might Surprise You". Huffington Post. Archived from the original on April 6, 2017. Retrieved March 18, 2017.
  36. ^ Karnofsky, Holden. "We Should Expect Good Giving To Be Hard (SSIR)". Stanford Social Innovation Review. Stanford University. Archived from the original on March 18, 2017. Retrieved March 18, 2017.
  37. ^ "Room for More Funding | GiveWell". www.givewell.org. Archived from the original on 2019-08-12. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  38. ^ Rosato, Donna; Wong, Grace (November 2011). "Best jobs for saving the world". CNN. Archived from the original on March 3, 2013. Retrieved February 28, 2013.
  39. ^ Todd, Benjamin. "Which Ethical Careers Make a Difference?: The Replaceability Issue in the Ethics of Career Choice". University of Oxford. Archived from the original on February 15, 2021. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  40. ^ "'Replaceability' isn't as important as you might think (or we've suggested)". 80,000 Hours. 2015-07-27. Archived from the original on 2019-06-27. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  41. ^ Burton, Paul (October 13, 2015). "Family Gives Away Half Their Income To Help Others". Archived from the original on September 30, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  42. ^ Geoghegan, Tom (December 13, 2010). "Toby Ord: Why I'm giving £1m to charity". BBC News. Archived from the original on May 13, 2013. Retrieved March 2, 2013.
  43. ^ MacAskill, William (November 26, 2015). "One of the most exciting new effective altruist organisations: An interview with David Goldberg of the Founders Pledge". 80,000 Hours. Archived from the original on September 21, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  44. ^ Butcher, Mike (June 9, 2015). "UK Tech Founders Take The Founders Pledge To 2%, Committing $28m+ To Good Causes". TechCrunch. Archived from the original on December 5, 2015. Retrieved December 5, 2015.
  45. ^ Paynter, Ben (2018-09-25). "Why nonprofits should be courting entrepreneurs as donors". Fast Company. Archived from the original on 2018-12-09. Retrieved 2018-12-09.
  46. ^ Oliver, Huw (6 October 2014). "'Effective altruists' are a new type of nice person". Vice. Archived from the original on 12 March 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  47. ^ from the original on 2021-02-15. Retrieved 2017-03-11.
  48. ^ a b Matthews, Dylan (November 28, 2018). "How to pick a career that counts". Vox. Archived from the original on December 24, 2019. Retrieved December 8, 2018.
  49. ^ "Want To Make An Impact With Your Work? Try Some Advice From 80,000 Hours". TechCrunch. August 4, 2015. Archived from the original on November 9, 2015. Retrieved October 31, 2015.
  50. ^ Alcorn, Stan (June 4, 2013). "How To Choose An Ethical Career (With Help From Oxford Philosophers)". Co.Exist. Fast Company Inc. Archived from the original on March 12, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  51. ^ "Meet the team". 80,000 Hours. Archived from the original on 2018-12-09. Retrieved 2018-12-09.
  52. ^ Todd, Benjamin (April 2017). "Why and how to earn to give". 80,000 Hours. Archived from the original on 2018-11-26. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  53. ^ Matthews, Dylan. "Join Wall Street. Save the world". The Washington Post. Archived from the original on March 15, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  54. ^ Todd, Benjamin (August 2017). "Is it ever okay to take a harmful job in order to do more good? An in-depth analysis". 80,000 Hours. Archived from the original on June 27, 2019. Retrieved June 27, 2019.
  55. ^ Brooks, David (June 3, 2013). "The Way to Produce a Person". The New York Times. Archived from the original on January 5, 2016. Retrieved July 7, 2015.
  56. ^ "'Earning to Give' Leads to Happiness". Yale Press Log. 2016-08-09. Archived from the original on 2017-04-05. Retrieved 2017-04-04.
  57. ^ a b Gobry, Pascal-Emmanuel (March 16, 2015). "Can Effective Altruism really change the world?". The Week. Archived from the original on March 21, 2015. Retrieved March 21, 2015.
  58. ^ a b Kissel, Joshua (January 31, 2017). "Effective Altruism and Anti-Capitalism: An Attempt at Reconciliation". Essays in Philosophy. Archived from the original on February 20, 2017. Retrieved February 19, 2017.
  59. ^ a b Matthews, Dylan (April 24, 2015). "You have $8 billion. You want to do as much good as possible. What do you do? Inside the Open Philanthropy Project". Vox. Archived from the original on August 24, 2017. Retrieved April 27, 2015.
  60. ^ Muehlhauser, Luke (July 8, 2013). "Four focus areas of effective altruism – Effective Altruism Forum". forum.effectivealtruism.org. Archived from the original on January 13, 2019. Retrieved January 12, 2019.
  61. ^ Karnofsky, Holden (August 13, 2013). "Effective Altruism". GiveWell. Archived from the original on August 18, 2015. Retrieved April 11, 2015.
  62. ^ Konduri, Vimal. "GiveWell Co-Founder Explains Effective Altruism Frameworks". The Harvard Crimson. The Harvard Crimson, Inc. Archived from the original on March 13, 2017. Retrieved March 10, 2017.
  63. ^ Wolfe, Alexandra (November 24, 2011). "Hedge Fund Analytics for Nonprofits". Bloomberg.com. Bloomberg LP. Archived from the original on March 16, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  64. ^ "Doing good by doing well". The Economist. Hearst Communications, Inc. Archived from the original on 27 December 2016. Retrieved 10 March 2017.
  65. Huffington Post. Archived
    from the original on May 18, 2015. Retrieved April 27, 2015.
  66. ^ Zhang, Linch (March 17, 2017). "How To Do Good: A Conversation With The World's Leading Ethicist". Huffington Post. Archived from the original on March 24, 2017. Retrieved June 1, 2017.
  67. ^ The Life You Can Save. "Our story - The Life You Can Save". Archived from the original on September 18, 2020. Retrieved September 18, 2020.
  68. ^ Weathers, Scott (29 February 2016). "Can 'effective altruism' change the world? It already has". Transformation. Archived from the original on 12 March 2017. Retrieved 11 March 2017.
  69. ^ "Focus Areas | Open Philanthropy Project". www.openphilanthropy.org. Archived from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  70. ^ Karnofsky, Holden (September 8, 2011). "Announcing GiveWell Labs". GiveWell. Archived from the original on July 2, 2015. Retrieved April 11, 2015.
  71. ^ "Who We Are | Open Philanthropy Project". www.openphilanthropy.org. Archived from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  72. ^ Karnofsky, Holden (August 20, 2014). "Open Philanthropy Project (formerly GiveWell Labs)". GiveWell. Archived from the original on August 16, 2015. Retrieved April 11, 2015.
  73. ^ Moses, Sue-Lynn (9 March 2016). "Leverage: Why This Silicon Valley Funder Is Doubling Down on a Beltway Think Tank". Inside Philanthropy. Archived from the original on 12 March 2017. Retrieved 11 March 2017.
  74. ^ Dullaghan, Neil (January 2, 2020). "EA Survey 2019 Series: Cause Prioritization". Effective Altruism Forum. Archived from the original on 2020-04-13. Retrieved 2020-04-15.
  75. ^ Whittlestone, Jess (November 16, 2017). "Cause Profile: Animal Welfare". Effective Altruism. Archived from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  76. ^ Banis, Davide. "New Book Draws Detailed Roadmap Of How We Can End Animal Farming". Forbes. Archived from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  77. from the original on 2017-08-01. Retrieved June 14, 2017.
  78. ^ Global Warming Climate Change and Farm Animal Welfare (PDF). Compassion in World Farming. 2008. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2016-05-27. Retrieved 2017-06-14.
  79. ^ Mood, Alison (2010). Worse things happen at sea: the welfare of wild-caught fish (PDF). fishcount.org.uk. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2017-05-19. Retrieved 2017-06-14.
  80. ^ a b Kristof, Nicholas (April 4, 2015). "The Trader Who Donates Half His Pay". The New York Times. Archived from the original on October 9, 2019. Retrieved April 11, 2015.
  81. ^ Matthews, Dylan (2021-04-12). "The wild frontier of animal welfare". Vox. Retrieved 2021-09-05.
  82. ^ ""Effective Altruism for Animals" Panel, Animal Studies". New York University Animal Studies Initiative. NYU. Archived from the original on 12 March 2017. Retrieved 11 March 2017.
  83. .
  84. ^ a b Piper, Kelsey (November 27, 2018). "Where will your donations do the most for animals?". Vox. Archived from the original on November 28, 2018. Retrieved December 8, 2018.
  85. ^ Daniel Engber, "Save the Chicken" Archived 2016-10-04 at the Wayback Machine, Slate, August 18, 2016.
  86. ^ Piper, Kelsey (2018-10-31). "Vegan diets are hard to sell. Animal activists might do better focused on corporate decisions, not people's plates". Vox. Archived from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  87. ^ "What We Do". Faunalytics. Archived from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  88. ^ Sigal, Samuel (2019-04-04). "Moral circle expansion: should animals, plants, and robots have the same rights as humans?". Vox. Retrieved 2021-12-01.
  89. ^ Witwicki, Kelly; Reese, Jacy. "Introducing Sentience Institute". Sentience Institute. Archived from the original on 5 August 2019. Retrieved 5 August 2019.
  90. ^ "The Importance of the Far Future". Effective Altruism Foundation. Effective Altruism Foundation. August 5, 2016. Archived from the original on March 12, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  91. (PDF) from the original on 2017-06-11. Retrieved 2017-06-15.
  92. ^ (PDF) from the original on 2020-04-06. Retrieved 2020-04-06.
  93. .
  94. ^ Klein, Ezra (6 December 2019). "Peter Singer on the lives you can save". Vox. Archived from the original on 6 May 2020. Retrieved 6 April 2020.
  95. ^ Todd, Benjamin (2017). "Why despite global progress, humanity is probably facing its most dangerous time ever". 80,000 Hours. Archived from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  96. ^ Rowe, Thomas; Beard, Simon (2018). "Probabilities, methodologies and the evidence base in existential risk assessments" (PDF). Working Paper, Centre for the Study of Existential Risk. Archived (PDF) from the original on 27 August 2018. Retrieved 26 August 2018.
  97. .
  98. ^ Guan, Melody (19 April 2015). "The New Social Movement of our Generation: Effective Altruism". Harvard Political Review. Archived from the original on 12 March 2017. Retrieved 11 March 2017.
  99. ^ Piper, Kelsey (2018-12-21). "The case for taking AI seriously as a threat to humanity". Vox. Archived from the original on 2019-01-13. Retrieved 2019-01-12.
  100. ^ Basulto, Dominic (July 7, 2015). "The very best ideas for preventing artificial intelligence from wrecking the planet". The Washington Post. Archived from the original on March 16, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  101. ^ a b c MacAskill, William (March 10, 2014). "The history of the term 'effective altruism'". forum.effectivealtruism.org. Archived from the original on February 20, 2020. Retrieved February 2, 2020.
  102. ^ Ram, Aliya (December 4, 2015). "The power and efficacy of effective altruism". Financial Times. Archived from the original on August 6, 2018. Retrieved February 14, 2018.
  103. ^
    OCLC 965456936
    .
  104. ^ a b c Rubenstein, Jennifer (14 December 2016). "The Lessons of Effective Altruism". Ethics & International Affairs. Archived from the original on 27 August 2018. Retrieved 26 August 2018.
  105. ^ Pitney, Nico (July 16, 2015). "Elon Musk To Address 'Nerd Altruists' At Google HQ". Huffington Post. Archived from the original on March 10, 2017. Retrieved March 11, 2017.
  106. ^ "Jaan Tallinn's Keynote - Effective Altruism Summit 2013". Exponential Times. November 13, 2013. Archived from the original on August 9, 2016. Retrieved April 11, 2015.
  107. from the original on June 22, 2017. Retrieved May 21, 2017.
  108. from the original on December 21, 2016. Retrieved May 21, 2017.
  109. from the original on February 1, 2020. Retrieved February 1, 2020.
  110. ^ Matthews, Dylan (October 15, 2018). "Future Perfect, explained". Vox. Archived from the original on December 25, 2019. Retrieved December 8, 2018.
  111. ^ "Future Perfect". www.vox.com. Archived from the original on February 1, 2020. Retrieved February 1, 2020.
  112. ^ Matthews, Dylan (December 17, 2019). "These are the charities where your money will do the most good". Vox. Archived from the original on August 29, 2019. Retrieved February 1, 2020.
  113. ^ Illing, Sean (March 8, 2019). "Want less poverty in the world? Empower women". Vox. Archived from the original on December 9, 2018. Retrieved February 1, 2020.
  114. ^ Yglesias, Matthew (January 8, 2020). "Installing air filters in classrooms has surprisingly large educational benefits: $1,000 can raise a class's test scores by as much as cutting class size by a third". Vox. Archived from the original on February 1, 2020. Retrieved February 1, 2020.
  115. ^ Piper, Kelsey (November 19, 2018). "How technological progress is making it likelier than ever that humans will destroy ourselves". Vox. Archived from the original on December 9, 2018. Retrieved December 9, 2018.
  116. ^ Walters, Helen. "The why and how of effective altruism: Peter Singer's talk visualized". TED Blog. Archived from the original on 2019-04-08. Retrieved 2016-06-29.
  117. ^ Matthews, Derek (January 3, 2017). "The whole philosophy community is mourning Derek Parfit. Here's why he mattered". Vox. Archived from the original on November 1, 2019. Retrieved December 1, 2019.
  118. ^ "Cari Tuna and Dustin Moskovitz: Young Silicon Valley billionaires pioneer new approach to philanthropy". The Washington Post. December 26, 2014. Archived from the original on August 25, 2019. Retrieved June 29, 2016.
  119. ^ "Global Priorities Institute opens at Oxford". April 5, 2018. Archived from the original on 25 November 2019. Retrieved 1 December 2019.
  120. ^ "Peter Singer: "The Most Good You Can Do" | Talks at Google". YouTube. Archived from the original on 2020-05-11. Retrieved 2019-04-18.
  121. ^ "News: Liv Boeree on Effective Altruism". www.pokerstrategy.com. Archived from the original on August 1, 2019. Retrieved April 11, 2017.
  122. ^ "Effective Altruism | Liv Boeree". www.livboeree.com. Archived from the original on August 1, 2019. Retrieved April 11, 2017.
  123. ^ Wiblin, Robert (July 26, 2018). "Prof Yew-Kwang Ng is a visionary economist who anticipated many key ideas in effective altruism decades ago. Here's his take on ethics and how to create a much happier world". 80,000 Hours. Archived from the original on 28 July 2018. Retrieved 1 December 2019.
  124. ^ "Kelsey Piper". EA Global. Archived from the original on 2021-01-30. Retrieved 2021-01-25.
  125. ^ Berger, Ken; Penna, Robert (November 25, 2013). "The Elitist Philanthropy of So-Called Effective Altruism". Stanford Social Innovation Review. Archived from the original on November 26, 2013. Retrieved November 26, 2013.
  126. ^ Snow, Mathew (August 25, 2015). "Against Charity". Jacobin. Archived from the original on August 28, 2015. Retrieved September 5, 2016.
  127. ^ (PDF) from the original on 13 September 2017. Retrieved 26 August 2018.
  128. .

Further reading

External links