Cosmological argument

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.

In the

causation, change, contingency or finitude.[1][2][3] In referring to reason and observation alone for its premises, and precluding revelation, this category of argument falls within the domain of natural theology
. A cosmological argument can also sometimes be referred to as an argument from universal causation, an argument from first cause, the causal argument or the prime mover argument.

The concept of causation is a principal underpinning idea in all cosmological arguments, particularly in affirming the necessity for a

First Cause. The latter is typically determined in philosophical analysis to be God, as identified within classical conceptions of theism
.

The origins of the argument date back to at least

Gottfried Leibniz and Samuel Clarke, itself an exposition of the Parmenidean causal principle that "nothing comes from nothing
".

History

Plato and Aristotle, depicted here in Raphael's The School of Athens, both developed first cause arguments.

Classical philosophy

The Laws (Book X), Plato posited that all movement in the world and the Cosmos was "imparted motion". This required a "self-originated motion" to set it in motion and to maintain it. In Timaeus
, Plato posited a "demiurge" of supreme wisdom and intelligence as the creator of the Cosmos.

Aristotle argued against the idea of a first cause, often confused with the idea of a "prime mover" or "

first uncaused cause – in his terminology, an efficient
first cause – an idea he considered a nonsensical flaw in the reasoning of the atomists.

Like Plato, Aristotle believed in an eternal

pantheon, but maintained a defense against dangerous charges of impiety.[10]

Late antiquity to the Islamic Golden Age

actual infinities. Thereupon, he formulated arguments in defense of temporal finitism, which underpinned his arguments for the existence of God. Philosopher Steven M. Duncan notes that Philoponus's ideas eventually received their fullest articulation "at the hands of Muslim and Jewish exponents of kalam", or medieval Islamic scholasticism.[13]

In the 11th century, Islamic philosopher

being, in which he distinguished between essence (māhiyya) and existence (wuǧūd).[14] He argued that the fact of existence could not be inferred from or accounted for by the essence of existing things, and that form and matter by themselves could not originate and interact with the movement of the universe or the progressive actualization of existing things. Thus, he reasoned that existence must be due to an agent cause that necessitates, imparts, gives, or adds existence to an essence. To do so, the cause must coexist with its effect and be an existing thing.[15]

Medieval Christian theology

Thomas Aquinas (c. 1225 – 1274) adapted and enhanced the argument he found in his reading of Aristotle, Avicenna (the Proof of the Truthful) and Maimonides to formulate one of the most influential versions of the cosmological argument.[16][17] His conception of the first cause was the idea that the universe must be caused by something that is itself uncaused, which he claimed is 'that which we call God':[16]

The second way is from the nature of the efficient cause. In the world of sense we find there is an order of efficient causes. There is no case known (neither is it, indeed, possible) in which a thing is found to be the efficient cause of itself; for so it would be prior to itself, which is impossible. Now in efficient causes it is not possible to go on to infinity, because in all efficient causes following in order, the first is the cause of the intermediate cause, and the intermediate is the cause of the ultimate cause, whether the intermediate cause be several, or only one. Now to take away the cause is to take away the effect. Therefore, if there be no first cause among efficient causes, there will be no ultimate, nor any intermediate cause. But if in efficient causes it is possible to go on to infinity, there will be no first efficient cause, neither will there be an ultimate effect, nor any intermediate efficient causes; all of which is plainly false. Therefore it is necessary to admit a first efficient cause, to which everyone gives the name of God.

Importantly, Aquinas's Five Ways, given the second question of his Summa Theologica, are not the entirety of Aquinas's demonstration that the Christian God exists. The Five Ways form only the beginning of Aquinas's Treatise on the Divine Nature.

General principles

The infinite regress

A regress is a series of related elements, arranged in some type of sequence of succession, examined in backwards succession (regression) from a fixed point of reference. Depending on the type of regress, this retrograde examination may take the form of

cause and effect, with each element in the series arising from causal activity of the prior member.[19] Some variants of the argument may also refer to temporal regress, wherein the elements are past events (discrete units of time) arranged in a temporal sequence.[4]

An

first cause) by arguing that its negation would lead to a vicious regress.[21] An infinite regress may be vicious due to various reasons:[22][1]

Accidental and essential ordering of causes

Aquinas refers to the distinction found in Aristotle's Physics (8.5) that a series of causes may either be accidental or essential,[25][26] though the designation of this terminology would follow later under John Duns Scotus at the turn of the 14th century.[27]

In an accidentally ordered series of causes, earlier members need not continue exerting causal activity (having done so to propagate the chain) for the series to continue. For example, in a generational line, ancestors need no longer exist for their offspring to continue the sequence of descent. In an essential series, prior members must maintain causal interrelationship for the series to continue: If a hand grips a stick that moves a rock along the ground, the rock would stop motion once the hand or stick ceases to exist.[28]

Based upon this distinction Frederick Copleston (1907–1994) characterises two types of causation: Causes in fieri, which cause an effect's becoming, or coming into existence, and causes in esse, which causally sustain an effect, in being, once it exists.[29]

Two specific properties of an essentially ordered series have significance in the context of the cosmological argument:[28]

  • A first cause is essential: Later members exercise no independent causal power in continuing the series. In the example illustrated above, the rock derives its causal power essentially from the stick, which derives its causal power essentially from the hand.
  • All members in the causal series must exist simultaneously in time, or timelessly.

Thomistic philosopher, R. P. Phillips comments on the characteristics of essential ordering:[30]

"Each member of the series of causes possesses being solely by virtue of the actual present operation of a superior cause ... Life is dependent inter alia on a certain atmospheric pressure, this again on the continual operation of physical forces, whose being and operation depends on the position of the earth in the solar system, which itself must endure relatively unchanged, a state of being which can only be continuously produced by a definite—if unknown—constitution of the material universe. This constitution, however, cannot be its own cause ... We are thus irresistibly led to posit a first efficient cause which, while itself uncaused, shall impart causality to a whole series."

Versions of the argument

Aquinas's argument from contingency

In the

uncaused cause,[31] he states: "... and this we understand to be God."[16]

Aquinas's argument from contingency is formulated as the Third Way (Q2, A3) in the Summa Theologica. It may be expressed as follows:[16]

  1. There exist contingent things, for which non-existence is possible.
  2. It is impossible for contingent things to always exist, so at some time they did not exist.
  3. Therefore, if all things are contingent, then nothing would exist now.
  4. There exists something rather than nothing.

He concludes thereupon that contingent beings are an insufficient explanation for the existence of other contingent beings. Furthermore, that there must exist a

necessary
being, whose non-existence is impossible, to explain the origination of all contingent beings.

  1. Therefore, there exists a necessary being.
  2. It is possible that a necessary being has a cause of its necessity in another necessary being.
  3. The derivation of necessity between beings cannot regress to infinity (being an essentially ordered causal series).
  4. Therefore, there exists a being that is necessary of itself, from which all necessity derives.
  5. That being is whom everyone calls God.

Leibnizian cosmological argument

In 1714, German philosopher

Gottfried Leibniz presented a variation of the cosmological argument based upon the principle of sufficient reason. He writes: "There can be found no fact that is true or existent, or any true proposition, without there being a sufficient reason for its being so and not otherwise, although we cannot know these reasons in most cases." Stating his argument succinctly:[32]

"Why is there something rather than nothing? The sufficient reason ... is found in a substance which ... is a necessary being bearing the reason for its existence within itself."

Alexander Pruss formulates the argument as follows:[33]

  1. Every contingent fact has an explanation.
  2. There is a contingent fact that includes all other contingent facts.
  3. Therefore, there is an explanation of this fact.
  4. This explanation must involve a necessary being.
  5. This necessary being is God.

Premise 1 expresses the principle of sufficient reason. In premise 2, Leibniz proposes the existence of a logical conjunction of all contingent facts, referred to in later literature as the Big Conjunctive Contingent Fact (BCCF), representing the sum total of contingent reality.[34] Premise 3 applies the principle of sufficient reason to the BCCF, given that it too, as a contingency, has a sufficient explanation. It follows, in statement 4, that the explanation of the BCCF must be necessary, not contingent, given that the BCCF incorporates all contingent facts. Statement 5 proposes that the necessary being explaining the totality of contingent facts is God.

Philosophers Joshua Rasmussen and T. Ryan Byerly have argued in defence of the inference from statement 4 to statement 5.[35][36]

Duns Scotus's metaphysical argument

At the turn of the 14th century, medieval Christian theologian

metaphysical argument for the existence of God inspired by Aquinas's argument of the unmoved mover.[37] Like other philosophers and theologians, Scotus believed that his statement for God's existence could be considered distinct to that of Aquinas. The form of the argument can be summarised as follows:[27]

  1. An effect cannot be produced by itself.
  2. An effect cannot be produced by nothing.
  3. A circle of causes is impossible.
  4. Therefore, an effect must be produced by something else.
  5. An accidentally ordered causal series cannot exist without an essentially ordered series.
  1. Each member in an accidentally ordered series (except a possible first) exists via causal activity of a prior member.
  2. That causal activity is exercised by virtue of a certain form.
  3. Therefore, that form is required by each member to effect causation.
  4. The form itself is not a member of the series.
  5. Therefore [c,d], accidentally ordered causes cannot exist without higher-order (essentially ordered) causes.
  1. An essentially ordered causal series cannot regress to infinity.
  2. Therefore [4,5,6], there exists a first agent.

Scotus affirms, in premise 5, that an accidentally ordered series of causes is impossible without higher-order laws and processes that govern the basic principles of accidental causation, which he characterises as essentially ordered causes.[38]

Premise 6 continues, in accordance with Aquinas's discourses on the Second Way and Third Way, that an essentially ordered series of causes cannot be an infinite regress.[39] On this, Scotus posits that, if it is merely possible that a first agent exists, then it is necessarily true that a first agent exists, given that the non-existence of a first agent entails the impossibility of its own existence (by virtue of being a first cause in the chain).[27] He argues further that it is not impossible for a being to exist that is causeless by virtue of ontological perfection.[40]

With the formulation of this argument, Scotus establishes the first component of his 'triple primacy': The characterisation of a being that is first in

final causality and pre-eminence, or maximal excellence, which he ascribes to God.[27]

Kalam cosmological argument

The Kalam cosmological argument's central thesis is the impossibility of an infinite

Christian theological scholarship in the 13th century.[42]

These ideas were revitalised for modern discourse by philosopher and theologian

deductive syllogism followed by further philosophical analysis.[4]

Initial syllogism

  1. Everything that begins to exist has a cause.
  2. The universe began to exist.
  3. Therefore, the universe has a cause.

Conceptual analysis of the conclusion

Craig argues that the cause of the universe

necessarily embodies specific properties in creating the universe ex nihilo and in effecting creation from a timeless state (implying free agency). Based upon this analysis, he appends a further premise and conclusion:[43]

  1. If the universe has a cause, then an uncaused, personal Creator of the universe exists who sans (without) the universe is beginningless, changeless, immaterial, timeless, spaceless and enormously powerful.
  2. Therefore, an uncaused, personal Creator of the universe exists, who sans the universe is beginningless, changeless, immaterial, timeless, spaceless and enormously powerful.

For scientific evidence of the finitude of the past, Craig refers to the

Borde-Guth-Vilenkin theorem, which posits a past boundary to cosmic inflation, and the general consensus on the standard model of cosmology, which refers to the origin of the universe in the Big Bang.[44][45]

For philosophical evidence, he cites

Tristram Shandy paradox to prove (respectively) the impossibility of actual infinites existing in reality and of forming an actual infinite by successive addition. He concludes that past events, in comprising a series of events that are instantiated in reality and formed by successive addition, cannot extend to an infinite past.[46]

Craig remarks upon the theological implications that follow from the conclusion of the argument:[47]

"... our whole universe was caused to exist by something beyond it and greater than it. For it is no secret that one of the most important conceptions of what theists mean by 'God' is Creator of heaven and earth."

Criticism and discourse

"What caused the first cause?"

Objections to the cosmological argument may question why a first cause is unique in that it does not require any causes. Critics contend that the concept of a first cause qualifies as special pleading, or that arguing for the first cause's exemption raises the question of why there should be a first cause at all.[48] Defenders maintain that this question is addressed by various formulations of the cosmological argument, emphasizing that none of its major iterations rests on the premise that everything requires a cause.[49]

Andrew Loke refers to the Kalam cosmological argument, in which the causal premise ("whatever begins to exist has a cause") stipulates that only things which begin to exist require a cause.[50] William Lane Craig asserts that—even if one posits a plurality of causes for the existence of the universe—a first uncaused cause is necessary, otherwise an infinite regress of causes would arise, which he argues is impossible.[4][1] Similarly, Edward Feser proposes, in accordance with Aquinas's discourses on the Second Way, that an essentially ordered series of causes cannot regress to infinity, even if it may be theoretically possible for accidentally ordered causes to do so.[51]

Various arguments have been presented to demonstrate the metaphysical impossibility of an actually infinite regress occurring in the

thought experiments such as Hilbert's Hotel, the tale of Tristram Shandy, and variations.[52][53]

"Does the universe need a cause?"

Craig maintains that the

nothing comes from nothing. If such intuitions are false, he argues it would be inexplicable why anything and everything does not randomly come into existence without a cause.[4] Yet, not all philosophers subscribe to the view of causality as a priori in justification. David Hume contends that the principle is rooted in experience, therefore within the category of a posteriori knowledge and subject to the problem of induction.[54]

Whereas J. L. Mackie argues that cause and effect cannot be extrapolated to the origins of the universe based upon our inductive experiences and intellectual preferences,[55] Craig proposes that causal laws are unrestricted metaphysical truths that are "not contingent upon the properties, causal powers, and dispositions of the natural kinds of substances which happen to exist".[56]

Identifying the first cause

Secular philosophers such as Michael Martin argue that a cosmological argument may establish the existence of a first cause, but falls short of identifying that cause as personal, or as God as defined within classical or other specific conceptions of theism.[57][1]

Defenders of the argument note that most formulations, such as by Aquinas, Duns Scotus and Craig, employ conceptual analysis to establish the identity of the cause. In Aquinas's Summa Theologica, the Prima Pars (First Part) is devoted predominantly to establishing the attributes of the cause, such as uniqueness, perfection and intelligence.[58] In Scotus's Ordinatio, his metaphysical argument is the first component of the 'triple primacy' through which he characterises the first cause as a being with the attributes of maximal excellence.[27]

Timeless origin of the universe

In the topic of cosmic origins and the standard model of cosmology, the initial singularity of the Big Bang is postulated to be the point at which space and time, as well as all matter and energy, came into existence.[59] J. Richard Gott and James E. Gunn assert that the question of "What was there before the Universe?" makes no sense and that the concept of before becomes meaningless when considering a timeless state. They add that questioning what occurred before the Big Bang is akin to questioning what is north of the North Pole.[59]

Craig refers to

membranes.[61] Feser also notes that versions of the cosmological argument presented by classical philosophers do not require a commitment to the Big Bang, or even to a cosmic origin.[62]

The Hume-Edwards principle

William L. Rowe characterises the Hume-Edwards principle, referring to arguments presented by David Hume, and later Paul Edwards, in their criticisms of the cosmological argument:[63]

"If the existence of every member of a set is explained, the existence of that set is thereby explained."

The principle stipulates that a causal series—even one that regresses to infinity—requires no explanatory causes beyond those that are members within that series. If every member of a series has a causal explanation within the sequence, the series in itself is explanatorily complete.[63] Thus, it rejects arguments, such as by Duns Scotus, for the existence of higher-order, efficient causes that govern the basic principles of material causation.[27] Notably, it contradicts Hume's own Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, in which the character Demea reflects that, even if a succession of causes is infinite, the very existence of the chain still requires a cause.[64][65]

Causal loop arguments

Some objections to the cosmological argument refer to the possibility of loops in the structure of cause and effect that would avoid the need for a first cause. Gott and Li refer to the curvature of spacetime and closed timelike curves as possible mechanisms by which the universe may bring about its own existence.[66] Richard Hanley contends that causal loops are neither logically nor physically impossible, remarking: "[In timed systems] the only possibly objectionable feature that all causal loops share is that coincidence is required to explain them."[67]

Andrew Loke argues that there is insufficient evidence to postulate a causal loop of the type that would avoid a first cause. He proposes that such a mechanism would suffer from the problem of vicious circularity, rendering it metaphysically impossible.[68]

See also

References

  1. ^ a b c d Reichenbach, Bruce (2022). "Cosmological Argument". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 14 January 2025.
  2. .
  3. .
  4. ^ .
  5. Koons, Robert (1997). "A New Look at the Cosmological Argument" (PDF). American Philosophical Quarterly. 34 (2). University of Illinois Press: 193–211. Archived from the original
    (PDF) on 2003-03-14. Retrieved 2015-03-27.
  6. .
  7. ^ Craig 2001, pp. 1–5, 13
  8. ^ Aristotle, Physics VIII, 4–6; Metaphysics XII, 1–6.
  9. ^ "Cosmological Argument for the Existence of God". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 2. 1967. p. 233.
  10. ^ "Review of: Aristotle and the Theology of the Living Immortals". Bryn Mawr Classical Review.
  11. ^ Gerson, Lloyd (2018). "Plotinus". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  12. ^ Proclus (1992). "Prop. 113". In E.R. Dodds (ed.). The Elements of Theology, A Revised Text. Clarendon.
  13. ^ Duncan, Steven (2010). Analytic Philosophy of Religion: its history since 1955. Humanities-Ebooks. p. 165.
  14. ^ Lizzini, Olga (2021). "Ibn Sina's Metaphysics". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 14 January 2025.
  15. ^ "Islam". Encyclopædia Britannica. 2007. Retrieved 2007-11-27.
  16. ^ a b c d e Aquinas, Thomas. "Summa Theologica: I Q2.3". New Advent.
  17. ^ Foutz, Scott. "An Examination of Thomas Aquinas' Cosmological Arguments as found in the Five Ways". Quodlibet Online Journal of Christian Theology and Philosophy.
  18. ^ a b Cameron, Ross (2018). "Infinite Regress Arguments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  19. ^ Huemer, Michael (2016). "13. Assessing Infinite Regress Arguments". Approaching Infinity. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: publisher location (link)
  20. ^ a b Maurin, Anna-Sofia (2007). "Infinite Regress – Virtue or Vice?". Hommage À Wlodek. Department of Philosophy, Lund University.
  21. .
  22. .
  23. .
  24. .
  25. ^ "Infinite Causal Regress and the Secunda Via in the Thought of Thomas Aquinas".
  26. ^ Floyd, Shawn. "Aquinas: Philosophical Theology 2.b.". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  27. ^ a b c d e f Williams, Thomas (2019). "John Duns Scotus". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 September 2024.
  28. ^ .
  29. ^ Joyce, George Hayward (1922). Principles of Natural Theology. New York: Longmans Green.
  30. . pp 284-285.
  31. ^ Aquinas was an ardent student of Aristotle's works, a significant number of which had only recently been translated into Latin by William of Moerbeke.
  32. ^ Rescher, Nicholas (1991). The Monadology: An Edition for Students. University of Pittsburgh Press.
  33. .
  34. .
  35. .
  36. .
  37. ^ Duns Scotus, John (1300). "Ordinatio I/D2/Q2B". The Logic Museum. Retrieved 27 September 2024.
  38. ^ Duns Scotus 1300 Paragraph 54: "Such an infinity of succession is impossible save from some nature that endures permanently, on which the whole succession and any part of it depend."
  39. ^ Duns Scotus 1300 Paragraph 53.
  40. ^ Duns Scotus 1300 Paragraph 53: "... an effective thing does not necessarily posit any imperfection; therefore it can be in something without imperfection. But if no cause is without dependence on something prior, it will not be in anything without imperfection."
  41. .
  42. ^ William Lane Craig. "The Kalam Cosmological Argument". Reasonable Faith.
  43. ^ Craig & Sinclair 2009, pp. 193–194
  44. .
  45. ^ Reichenbach 2022 7.4-7.5
  46. ^ Reichenbach 2022 7.2-7.3
  47. .
  48. ^ Reichenbach 2022 4.5
  49. .
  50. .
  51. .
  52. ^ Loke 2017, Chapters 2-3
  53. .
  54. ^ "David Hume: Causation". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2025-01-14.
  55. .
  56. ^ a b William Lane Craig. "Must the Beginning of the Universe Have a Personal Cause?: A Rejoinder". Reasonable Faith.
  57. .
  58. ^ Aquinas, Thomas. "Summa Theologica: Prima Pars". New Advent.
  59. ^
    JSTOR 24950306
    . Retrieved December 10, 2023.
  60. ^ Craig, William Lane. "Creation and Simultaneous Causation". Reasonable Faith.
  61. ^ Britt, Robert R. (April 18, 2001). "Brane-Storm | Challenges Part of Big Bang Theory". Space.com. Archived from the original on 11 May 2008. Retrieved June 21, 2008.
  62. .
  63. ^ a b Alexander R. Pruss, The Hume-Edwards Principle and the Cosmological Argument, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion
  64. ^ Hume, David (1779). Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. London: Penguin Books.
  65. S2CID 189828318
    .
  66. .
  67. .
  68. .