Aristotle
Aristotle | ||
---|---|---|
Ἀριστοτέλης | ||
School Peripatetic school | | |
Notable students | Alexander the Great, Theophrastus, Aristoxenus | |
Main interests | ||
Notable works | ||
Notable ideas | Aristotelianism
Theoretical philosophy
Natural philosophy
Practical philosophy |
Aristotle
Little is known about Aristotle's life. He was born in the city of
Though Aristotle wrote many treatises and dialogues for publication, only around a third of his original output has survived, none of it intended for publication. Aristotle provided a complex synthesis of the various philosophies existing prior to him. His teachings and methods of inquiry have had a significant impact across the world, and remain a subject of contemporary philosophical discussion.
Aristotle's views profoundly shaped
Aristotle was revered among medieval Muslim scholars as "The First Teacher", and among medieval Christians like
Life
In general, the details of Aristotle's life are not well-established. The biographies written in ancient times are often speculative and historians only agree on a few salient points.
At the age of seventeen or eighteen, Aristotle moved to

In 343/42 BC, Aristotle was invited to
As a metic, Aristotle could not own property in Athens and thus rented a building known as the Lyceum (named after the sacred grove of Apollo Lykeios), in which he established his own school.[30] The building included a gymnasium and a colonnade (peripatos), from which the school acquired the name Peripatetic.[31] Aristotle conducted courses and research at the school for the next twelve years. He often lectured small groups of distinguished students and, along with some of them, such as Theophrastus, Eudemus, and Aristoxenus, Aristotle built a large library which included manuscripts, maps, and museum objects.[32] While in Athens, his wife Pythias died and Aristotle became involved with Herpyllis of Stagira. They had a son whom Aristotle named after his father, Nicomachus.[33] This period in Athens, between 335 and 323 BC, is when Aristotle is believed to have composed many of his philosophical works.[34] He wrote many dialogues, of which only fragments have survived. Those works that have survived are in treatise form and were not, for the most part, intended for widespread publication; they are generally thought to be lecture aids for his students. His most important treatises include Physics, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics, Politics, On the Soul and Poetics. Aristotle studied and made significant contributions to "logic, metaphysics, mathematics, physics, biology, botany, ethics, politics, agriculture, medicine, dance, and theatre."[35]
While Alexander deeply admired Aristotle, near the end of his life, the two men became estranged having diverging opinions over issues, like the optimal administration of city-states, the treatment of conquered populations, such as the Persians, and philosophical questions, like the definition of braveness.
Theoretical philosophy
Logic
With the
Organon

Most of Aristotle's work is probably not in its original form, because it was most likely edited by students and later lecturers. The logical works of Aristotle were compiled into a set of six books called the Organon around 40 BC by Andronicus of Rhodes or others among his followers.[49] The books are:
- Categories
- On Interpretation
- Prior Analytics
- Posterior Analytics
- Topics
- On Sophistical Refutations
The order of the books (or the teachings from which they are composed) is not certain, but this list was derived from analysis of Aristotle's writings. It goes from the basics, the analysis of simple terms in the Categories, the analysis of propositions and their elementary relations in On Interpretation, to the study of more complex forms, namely, syllogisms and demonstration (in the Analytics)[50][51] and dialectics (in the Topics and Sophistical Refutations). The first three treatises form the core of the logical theory stricto sensu: the grammar of the language of logic and the correct rules of reasoning. The Rhetoric is not conventionally included, but it states that it relies on the Topics.[52]
Syllogism
In words | In terms[G] |
In equations[H] |
---|---|---|
All men are mortal. All Greeks are men. ∴ All Greeks are mortal. |
M a P S a M S a P |
![]() |
What is today called Aristotelian logic with its types of syllogism (methods of logical argument),[53] Aristotle himself would have labelled "analytics". The term "logic" he reserved to mean dialectics.[55][56]
Demonstration
Aristotle's Posterior Analytics contains his account of demonstration, or demonstrative knowledge, what would today be considered the study of epistemology rather than logic, but which for Aristotle is deeply connected with his account of syllogism.[52] For Aristotle, knowledge is that which is necessarily the case, along with the study of causes.[52]
Metaphysics
The word "metaphysics" comes from the title of a collection of works by Aristotle bearing that title. However, Aristotle himself did not use that term himself, which is due to a later compiler, but instead called it "first philosophy" or theology.[57] He distinguished this as "the study of being qua being" which, as opposed to other studies of being, such as mathematics and natural science, studies that which is eternal, unchanging, and immaterial.[57] He wrote in his Metaphysics (1026a16):
If there were no other independent things besides the composite natural ones, the study of nature would be the primary kind of knowledge; but if there is some motionless independent thing, the knowledge of this precedes it and is first philosophy, and it is universal in just this way, because it is first. And it belongs to this sort of philosophy to study being as being, both what it is and what belongs to it just by virtue of being.[58]
Substance
Aristotle examines the concepts of
Moderate realism
Like his teacher Plato, Aristotle's philosophy aims at the universal. Aristotle's ontology has the universal (katholou) exist in a lesser sense than particulars (kath' hekaston), things in the world, whereas for Plato the universal is a realer, separately existing form which particular things merely imitate. For Aristotle, universals still exist, but are only encountered when "instantiated" in a particular substance.[57]
In addition, Aristotle disagreed with Plato about the location of universals. Where Plato spoke of the forms as existing separately from the things that participate in them, Aristotle maintained that universals are multiply located. So, according to Aristotle, the form of apple exists within each apple, rather than in the world of the forms.[57][60]
Potentiality and actuality
Concerning the nature of change (kinesis) and its causes, as he outlines in his Physics and On Generation and Corruption (319b–320a), he distinguishes coming-to-be (genesis, also translated as 'generation') from:
- growth and diminution, which is change in quantity;
- locomotion, which is change in space; and
- alteration, which is change in quality.

Coming-to-be is a change where the substrate of the thing that has undergone the change has itself changed. In that particular change he introduces the concept of potentiality (
For that for the sake of which (to hou heneka) a thing is, is its principle, and the becoming is for the sake of the end; and the actuality is the end, and it is for the sake of this that the potentiality is acquired. For animals do not see in order that they may have sight, but they have sight that they may see.[61]
In summary, the matter used to make a house has potentiality to be a house and both the activity of building and the form of the final house are actualities, which is also a
Natural philosophy
Aristotle's "natural philosophy" spans a wide range of natural phenomena including those now covered by physics, biology and other natural sciences.[63] In Aristotle's terminology, "natural philosophy" is a branch of philosophy examining the phenomena of the natural world, and includes fields that would be regarded today as physics, biology and other natural sciences. Aristotle's work encompassed virtually all facets of intellectual inquiry. Aristotle makes philosophy in the broad sense coextensive with reasoning, which he also would describe as "science". However, his use of the term science carries a different meaning than that covered by the term "scientific method". For Aristotle, "all science (dianoia) is either practical, poetical or theoretical" (Metaphysics 1025b25). His practical science includes ethics and politics; his poetical science means the study of fine arts including poetry; his theoretical science covers physics, mathematics and metaphysics.[63]
Physics

Five elements
In his
Element | Hot/Cold | Wet/Dry | Motion | Modern state of matter |
---|---|---|---|---|
Earth | Cold | Dry | Down | Solid |
Water | Cold | Wet | Down | Liquid |
Air | Hot | Wet | Up | Gas |
Fire | Hot | Dry | Up | Plasma |
Aether | (divine substance) |
None | Circular (in heavens) |
Vacuum |
Motion
Aristotle describes two kinds of motion: "violent" or "unnatural motion", such as that of a thrown stone, in the Physics (254b10), and "natural motion", such as of a falling object, in On the Heavens (300a20). In violent motion, as soon as the agent stops causing it, the motion stops also: in other words, the natural state of an object is to be at rest,[65][I] since Aristotle does not address friction.[66] With this understanding, it can be observed that, as Aristotle stated, heavy objects (on the ground, say) require more force to make them move; and objects pushed with greater force move faster.[67][J] This would imply the equation[67]
- ,
incorrect in modern physics.[67]
Natural motion depends on the element concerned: the aether naturally moves in a circle around the heavens,[K] while the 4 Empedoclean elements move vertically up (like fire, as is observed) or down (like earth) towards their natural resting places.[68][66][L]

In the Physics (215a25), Aristotle effectively states a quantitative law, that the speed, v, of a falling body is proportional (say, with constant c) to its weight, W, and inversely proportional to the density,[M] ρ, of the fluid in which it is falling:;[68][66]
Aristotle implies that in a vacuum the speed of fall would become infinite, and concludes from this apparent absurdity that a vacuum is not possible.[68][66] Opinions have varied on whether Aristotle intended to state quantitative laws. Henri Carteron held the "extreme view"[66] that Aristotle's concept of force was basically qualitative,[69] but other authors reject this.[66]
Archimedes corrected Aristotle's theory that bodies move towards their natural resting places; metal boats can float if they displace enough water; floating depends in Archimedes' scheme on the mass and volume of the object, not, as Aristotle thought, its elementary composition.[68]
Aristotle's writings on motion remained influential until the
Newton's "forced" motion corresponds to Aristotle's "violent" motion with its external agent, but Aristotle's assumption that the agent's effect stops immediately it stops acting (e.g., the ball leaves the thrower's hand) has awkward consequences: he has to suppose that surrounding fluid helps to push the ball along to make it continue to rise even though the hand is no longer acting on it, resulting in the Medieval theory of impetus.[68]
Four causes

Aristotle distinguished between four different "causes"(
- The material cause describes the material out of which something is composed. Thus the material cause of a wooden table is the wood it is made of.[71]
- The formal cause is its form, i.e., the arrangement of that matter, the design of the table independent of the specific material it is made of.[71]
- The efficient cause is "the primary source", the modern definition of "cause" as either the agent or agency of particular events or states of affairs. In the case of two dominoes, when the first is knocked over it causes the second to fall.[71] In the case of an animal, this agency is a combination of how it develops from the egg, and how its body functions.[73]
- The final cause (telos) is its purpose, the reason why it exists or is done, or function that something is supposed to serve.[71] In the case of living things, it implies adaptation to a particular way of life.[73]
Optics
Aristotle was aware of Pythagorean optics.[74] He used optics in his Meteorology, treating it as a science.[75] He viewed optics as stating the laws of sight, thus combining what is now treated as physics and biology.[76] The process of seeing involved the movement of a visible form from the thing seen through the air (or other medium) to the eye, where the form comes to rest. Aristotle does not analyse the nature of this movement; he does not anticipate geometrical optics.[77]
Chance and spontaneity
According to Aristotle, spontaneity and chance are causes of some things, distinguishable from other types of cause such as simple necessity. Chance as an incidental cause lies in the realm of accidental things, "from what is spontaneous". There is also more a specific kind of chance, which Aristotle names "luck", that only applies to people's moral choices.[78][79]
Astronomy
In astronomy, Aristotle refuted Democritus's claim that the Milky Way was made up of "those stars which are shaded by the earth from the sun's rays," pointing out partly correctly that if "the size of the sun is greater than that of the earth and the distance of the stars from the earth many times greater than that of the sun, then... the sun shines on all the stars and the earth screens none of them."[80] He also wrote descriptions of comets, including the Great Comet of 371 BC.[81]
Geology and natural sciences
Aristotle was one of the first people to record any
Meteorologica lends its name to the modern study of meteorology, but its modern usage diverges from the content of Aristotle's ancient treatise on
Aristotle also made many observations about the hydrologic cycle. For example, he made some of the earliest observations about desalination: he observed early – and correctly – that when seawater is heated, freshwater evaporates and that the oceans are then replenished by the cycle of rainfall and river runoff ("I have proved by experiment that salt water evaporated forms fresh and the vapor does not when it condenses condense into sea water again.")[86]
Biology
Empirical research
Aristotle was the first person to study biology systematically,[87] and biology forms a large part of his writings. He spent two years observing and describing the zoology of Lesbos and the surrounding seas, including in particular the Pyrrha lagoon in the centre of Lesbos.[88][89] His data in History of Animals, Generation of Animals, Movement of Animals, and Parts of Animals are from his own observations,[90] statements by knowledgeable people such as beekeepers and fishermen, and accounts by travellers.[91] His apparent emphasis on animals rather than plants is a historical accident: his works on botany have been lost, but two books on plants by his pupil Theophrastus have survived.[92]
Aristotle reports on sea-life from observation on Lesbos and the catches of fishermen. He describes the
He notes that an animal's structure is well matched to function so the
Scientific style
Aristotle did not do experiments in the modern sense.[100] He made observations, or at most investigative procedures like dissection.[101] In Generation of Animals, he opens a fertilized hen's egg to see the embryo's heart beating inside.[102][103]
Instead, he systematically gathered data, discovering patterns common to whole groups of animals, and inferring possible causal explanations from these.[104][105] This style is common in modern biology when large amounts of data become available in a new field, such as genomics. This sets out testable hypotheses and constructs a narrative explanation of what is observed. In this sense, Aristotle's biology is scientific.[104]
From his data, Aristotle inferred
Classification of living things
Aristotle distinguished about 500
Group | Examples (given by Aristotle) |
Blood | Legs | Souls (Rational, Sensitive, Vegetative) |
Qualities (Hot–Cold, Wet–Dry) |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
Man | Man | with blood | 2 legs | R, S, V | Hot, Wet |
Live-bearing tetrapods | Cat, hare | with blood | 4 legs | S, V | Hot, Wet |
Cetaceans |
Dolphin, whale | with blood | none | S, V | Hot, Wet |
Birds |
Bee-eater, nightjar | with blood | 2 legs | S, V | Hot, Wet, except Dry eggs |
Egg-laying tetrapods | Chameleon, crocodile | with blood | 4 legs | S, V | Cold, Wet except scales, eggs |
Snakes |
Water snake, Ottoman viper |
with blood | none | S, V | Cold, Wet except scales, eggs |
Egg-laying fishes | Sea bass, parrotfish | with blood | none | S, V | Cold, Wet, including eggs |
(Among the egg-laying fishes): placental selachians |
Shark, skate | with blood | none | S, V | Cold, Wet, but placenta like tetrapods |
Crustaceans |
Shrimp, crab | without | many legs | S, V | Cold, Wet except shell |
Cephalopods |
Squid, octopus | without | tentacles | S, V | Cold, Wet |
Hard-shelled animals |
Cockle, trumpet snail | without | none | S, V | Cold, Dry (mineral shell) |
Larva-bearing insects | Ant, cicada | without | 6 legs | S, V | Cold, Dry |
Spontaneously generating | Sponges, worms |
without | none | S, V | Cold, Wet or Dry, from earth |
Plants |
Fig | without | none | V | Cold, Dry |
Minerals | Iron | without | none | none | Cold, Dry |
Psychology
Soul

Aristotle's psychology, in his treatise On the Soul (peri psychēs), posits three kinds of soul (psyches): the vegetative, sensitive, and rational. Humans have all three. The vegetative soul is concerned with growth and nourishment. The sensitive soul experiences sensations and movement. The uniquely human, rational soul receives forms of things and compares them using the nous (intellect) and logos (reason).[118]
For Aristotle, the soul is the form of a living being. Because all beings are composites of form and matter, the form of living beings is that which endows them with what is specific to living beings, e.g. the ability to initiate movement.[119] In contrast to earlier philosophers, but in accordance with the Egyptians, he placed the rational soul in the heart.[120] Aristotle distinguished sensation and thought, unlike previous philosophers except for Alcmaeon.[121]
In On the Soul, Aristotle criticizes Plato's theory of the soul and develops his own in response. Firstly he criticises Plato's Timaeus which holds the soul takes up space and can come into physical contact with bodies.[122] 20th-century scholarship held that Aristotle had here misinterpreted Plato.[123] Aristotle also argued that Plato's view of reincarnation entails that a soul and its body can be mis-matched; in principle, Aristotle alleges, any soul can go with any body, according to Plato's theory.[124]
Memory
According to Aristotle in On the Soul, memory is the ability to hold a perceived experience in the mind and to distinguish between the internal "appearance" and a past occurrence.[125] A memory is a mental picture (phantasm) that can be recovered. An impression is left on a semi-fluid bodily organ that undergoes changes in order to make a memory. A memory occurs when stimuli such as sights or sounds are so complex that the nervous system cannot receive them all at once. These changes are the same as those involved in sensation, 'common sense', and thinking.[126][127]
Aristotle uses the term 'memory' for the actual retaining of an experience in the impression that develops from sensation, and for the intellectual anxiety that comes with the impression because it is formed at a particular time and processing specific contents. Memory is of the past, prediction is of the future, and sensation is of the present. Retrieval of impressions cannot be performed suddenly. A transitional channel is needed and located in past experiences, both for previous experience and present experience.[128]
Because Aristotle believes people perceive all kinds of sense perceptions as impressions, people continually weave together new impressions of experiences. To search for impressions, people search memory itself.[129] Within memory, if an experience is offered instead of a specific memory, that person will reject this experience until they find what they are looking for. Recollection occurs when a retrieved experience naturally follows another. If the chain of "images" is needed, one memory stimulates the next. When people recall experiences, they stimulate certain previous experiences until they reach the one that is needed.[130] Recollection is thus the self-directed activity of retrieving information stored in a memory impression.[131] Only humans can remember impressions of intellectual activity, such as numbers and words. Animals that have perception of time can retrieve memories of their past observations. Remembering involves only perception of the things remembered and of the time passed.[132]

Aristotle believed the chain of thought that achieves recollection of impressions was connected systematically in relationships such as similarity, contrast, and contiguity, described in his laws of association. Aristotle believed that past experiences are hidden within the mind. A force operates to awaken the hidden material to bring up the actual experience. Association is the power innate in a mental state, which operates upon the unexpressed remains of former experiences, allowing them to be recalled.[133][134]
Dreams
Aristotle describes sleep in On Sleep and Wakefulness.[135] It is a result of overuse of the senses[136] or of digestion,[137] and is vital to the body.[136] While a person is asleep, the critical activities, which include thinking, sensing, recalling and remembering, do not function. Since a person cannot sense during sleep, they cannot have desire. However, the senses work during sleep,[136] albeit differently.[135]
Dreams do not involve sensing a stimulus. Sensation is involved, but in an altered manner.[136] Aristotle explains that when a person stares at a moving stimulus such as the waves in a body of water, and then looks away, the next thing they look at appears to have a wavelike motion. When a person perceives a stimulus and it is no longer the focus of their attention, it leaves an impression.[135] When the body is awake, a person constantly encounters new stimuli and so the impressions of previous stimuli are ignored.[136] However, during sleep the impressions made throughout the day are noticed, free of distractions.[135] So, dreams result from these lasting impressions. Since impressions are all that are left, dreams do not resemble waking experience.[138] During sleep, a person is in an altered state of mind, like a person who is overtaken by strong feelings. For example, a person who has a strong infatuation with someone may begin to think they see that person everywhere. Since a person sleeping is in a suggestible state and unable to make judgements, they become easily deceived by what appears in their dreams, like the infatuated person.[135] This leads them to believe the dream is real, even when the dreams are absurd.[135] In De Anima iii 3, Aristotle ascribes the ability to create, to store, and to recall images to the faculty of imagination, phantasia.[119]
One component of Aristotle's theory disagrees with previously held beliefs. He claimed that dreams are not foretelling and not sent by a divine being. Aristotle reasoned that instances in which dreams resemble future events are simply coincidences.[139] Any sensory experience perceived while a person is asleep, such as actually hearing a door close, does not qualify as part of a dream. Images of dreams must be a result of lasting impressions of waking sensory experiences.[138]
Practical philosophy
Aristotle's practical philosophy covers areas such as ethics, politics, economics, and rhetoric.[63]
Too little | Virtuous mean | Too much |
---|---|---|
Humbleness | High-mindedness | Vainglory |
Lack of purpose | Right ambition | Over-ambition |
Spiritlessness | Good temper | Irascibility |
Rudeness | Civility | Obsequiousness |
Cowardice | Courage | Rashness |
Insensibility | Self-control | Intemperance |
Sarcasm | Sincerity | Boastfulness |
Boorishness | Wit | Buffoonery |
Callousness | Just resentment | Spitefulness |
Pettiness | Generosity | Vulgarity |
Meanness | Liberality | Wastefulness |
Ethics
Aristotle was a virtue ethicist who considered ethics to be a practical rather than theoretical study, i.e., one aimed at becoming good and doing good rather than knowing for its own sake. He wrote several treatises on ethics, most notably including the Nicomachean Ethics.[140]
Aristotle taught that virtue has to do with the proper function (ergon) of a thing. An eye is only a good eye in so much as it can see because the proper function of an eye is sight. Aristotle reasoned that humans must have a function specific to humans, and that this function must be an activity of the
Aristotle taught that to achieve a virtuous and potentially happy character requires a first stage of having the fortune to be habituated, not deliberately, but by teachers, and experience, leading to a later stage in which one consciously chooses to do the best things, becoming the phronimos or virtuous man. When the best people come to live life this way their practical wisdom (phronesis) and their intellect (nous) can develop with each other towards the highest possible human virtue, the wisdom of an accomplished theoretical or speculative thinker, or in other words, a philosopher.[142]
Politics
In addition to his works on ethics, which address the individual, Aristotle addressed the city in his work titled Politics. Aristotle considered the city to be a natural community. Moreover, he considered the city to be prior in importance to the family, which in turn is prior to the individual, "for the whole must of necessity be prior to the part".[143] He famously stated that "man is by nature a political animal" and argued that humanity's defining factor among others in the animal kingdom is its rationality.[144] Aristotle conceived of politics as being like an organism rather than like a machine, and as a collection of parts, none of which can exist without the others. Aristotle's conception of the city is organic, and he is considered one of the first to conceive of the city in this manner.[145]

The common modern understanding of a political community as a modern state is quite different from Aristotle's understanding. Although he was aware of the existence and potential of larger empires, the natural community according to Aristotle was the city (polis) which functions as a political "community" or "partnership" (koinōnia). The aim of the city is not just to avoid injustice or for economic stability, but rather to allow at least some citizens the possibility to live a good life, and to perform beautiful acts: "The political partnership must be regarded, therefore, as being for the sake of noble actions, not for the sake of living together." This is distinguished from modern approaches, beginning with social contract theory, according to which individuals leave the state of nature because of "fear of violent death" or its "inconveniences".[O]
In Protrepticus, the character 'Aristotle' states:[146]
For we all agree that the most excellent man should rule, i.e., the supreme by nature, and that the law rules and alone is authoritative; but the law is a kind of intelligence, i.e. a discourse based on intelligence. And again, what standard do we have, what criterion of good things, that is more precise than the intelligent man? For all that this man will choose, if the choice is based on his knowledge, are good things and their contraries are bad. And since everybody chooses most of all what conforms to their own proper dispositions (a just man choosing to live justly, a man with bravery to live bravely, likewise a self-controlled man to live with self-control), it is clear that the intelligent man will choose most of all to be intelligent; for this is the function of that capacity. Hence it's evident that, according to the most authoritative judgment, intelligence is supreme among goods.[146]
As Plato's disciple Aristotle was rather critical concerning democracy and, following the outline of certain ideas from Plato's Statesman, he developed a coherent theory of integrating various forms of power into a so-called mixed state:
It is ... constitutional to take ... from oligarchy that offices are to be elected, and from democracy that this is not to be on a property-qualification. This then is the mode of the mixture; and the mark of a good mixture of democracy and oligarchy is when it is possible to speak of the same constitution as a democracy and as an oligarchy.
— Aristotle. Politics, Book 4, 1294b.10–18
Economics
Aristotle made substantial contributions to
Aristotle's discussions on retail and interest was a major influence on economic thought in the Middle Ages. He had a low opinion of retail, believing that contrary to using money to procure things one needs in managing the household, retail trade seeks to make a profit. It thus uses goods as a means to an end, rather than as an end unto itself. He believed that retail trade was in this way unnatural. Similarly, Aristotle considered making a profit through interest unnatural, as it makes a gain out of the money itself, and not from its use.[148]
Aristotle gave a summary of the function of money that was perhaps remarkably precocious for his time. He wrote that because it is impossible to determine the value of every good through a count of the number of other goods it is worth, the necessity arises of a single universal standard of measurement. Money thus allows for the association of different goods and makes them "commensurable".[148] He goes on to state that money is also useful for future exchange, making it a sort of security. That is, "if we do not want a thing now, we shall be able to get it when we do want it".[148]
Rhetoric
Part of a series on |
Rhetoric |
---|
![]() |
Aristotle's Rhetoric proposes that a speaker can use three basic kinds of appeals to persuade his audience: ethos (an appeal to the speaker's character), pathos (an appeal to the audience's emotion), and logos (an appeal to logical reasoning).[149] He also categorizes rhetoric into three genres: epideictic (ceremonial speeches dealing with praise or blame), forensic (judicial speeches over guilt or innocence), and deliberative (speeches calling on an audience to decide on an issue).[150] Aristotle also outlines two kinds of rhetorical proofs: enthymeme (proof by syllogism) and paradeigma (proof by example).[151]
Poetics
Aristotle writes in his Poetics that
While it is believed that Aristotle's Poetics originally comprised two books – one on comedy and one on tragedy – only the portion that focuses on tragedy has survived. Aristotle taught that tragedy is composed of six elements: plot-structure, character, style, thought, spectacle, and lyric poetry.
Legacy

More than 2300 years after his death, Aristotle remains one of the most influential people who ever lived.[161][162][163] He contributed to almost every field of human knowledge then in existence, and he was the founder of many new fields. According to the philosopher Bryan Magee, "it is doubtful whether any human being has ever known as much as he did".[164] Aristotle has been regarded as the first scientist.[165][166]
Aristotle was the founder of term logic, pioneered the study of zoology, and benefited future scientists and philosophers through his contributions to the scientific method.[40][167][168] Taneli Kukkonen, observes that his achievement in founding two sciences is unmatched, and his reach in influencing "every branch of intellectual enterprise" including Western ethical and political theory, theology, rhetoric, and literary analysis is equally long. As a result, Kukkonen argues, any analysis of reality today "will almost certainly carry Aristotelian overtones ... evidence of an exceptionally forceful mind."[168] Jonathan Barnes wrote that "an account of Aristotle's intellectual afterlife would be little less than a history of European thought".[169]
Aristotle has been called the father of logic, biology, political science, zoology, embryology, natural law, scientific method, rhetoric, psychology, realism, criticism, individualism, teleology, and meteorology.[171]
The scholar Taneli Kukkonen writes that "in the best 20th-century scholarship Aristotle comes alive as a thinker wrestling with the full weight of the Greek philosophical tradition."[168] What follows is an overview of the transmission and influence of his texts and ideas into the modern era.[172][173]
Ancient
Hellenistic period

The immediate influence of Aristotle's work was felt as the
Aristotle's pupil and successor,
Under the
Early Roman empire
In antiquity, Aristotle's writings were divisible into two groups; the "
The primary way that ancient philosophers in the Roman empire engaged with Aristotle's technical work was via philosophical commentary; interpretation and explication of the text of Aristotle along with their own synthesis and views on the topics discussed by Aristotle. The peripatetic commentary tradition began with Boethus of Sidon in the 1st century BC and reached its peak at the end of the 2nd century AD with Alexander of Aphrodisias, who was appointed to the official Imperial chair of Aristotelian philosophy established by Marcus Aurelius, many of whose commentaries still survive.[184]
Late antiquity
In the 3rd century, Neoplatonism emerged as the dominant philosophical school. The Neoplatonists saw all subsequent philosophical systems after Plato, including Aristotle's, as developments on Plato's philosophy, and sought to explain how Plato and Aristotle were in agreement, even on subjects where they appeared to disagree, and included Aristotle's logical and physical works in their school curriculum as introductory works that needed to be mastered before the study of Plato himself. This study program began with the Categories, which the Neoplatonist philosopher Porphyry of Tyre wrote an introduction to, called Isagoge, which went on to influence subsequent philosophy in late antiquity and the medieval period. Later Neoplatonists in Athens and Alexandria including Syrianus, Ammonius Hermiae, Olympiodorus the Younger and Simplicius of Cilicia wrote further commentaries on Aristotle from a Platonist perspective which are still extant, with Simplicius compiling many of the lost works of his predecessors into massive commentaries that survey the entire Neoplatonic tradition.[184]
With the rise of Christianity and closure of the pagan schools by the order of
Medieval
Medieval Byzantine empire
After a hiatus of several centuries, formal commentary by
Medieval Islamic world

Aristotle's works also underwent a revival in the
Medieval Judaism
Medieval Western Europe

With the loss of the study of ancient Greek in the early
After the
According to scholar Roger Theodore Lafferty,
Modern era
Early Modern science
In the
18th and 19th-century science
The English mathematician George Boole fully accepted Aristotle's logic, but decided "to go under, over, and beyond" it with his system of algebraic logic in his 1854 book The Laws of Thought. This gives logic a mathematical foundation with equations, enables it to solve equations as well as check validity, and allows it to handle a wider class of problems by expanding propositions of any number of terms, not just two.[216]
Charles Darwin regarded Aristotle as the most important contributor to the subject of biology. In an 1882 letter he wrote that "Linnaeus and Cuvier have been my two gods, though in very different ways, but they were mere schoolboys to old Aristotle".[217][218] Also, in later editions of the book "On the Origin of Species', Darwin traced evolutionary ideas as far back as Aristotle;[219] the text he cites is a summary by Aristotle of the ideas of the earlier Greek philosopher Empedocles.[220]
Present science
The philosopher Bertrand Russell claims that "almost every serious intellectual advance has had to begin with an attack on some Aristotelian doctrine". Russell calls Aristotle's ethics "repulsive", and labelled his logic "as definitely antiquated as Ptolemaic astronomy". Russell states that these errors make it difficult to do historical justice to Aristotle, until one remembers what an advance he made upon all of his predecessors.[172]
The Dutch historian of science Eduard Jan Dijksterhuis writes that Aristotle and his predecessors showed the difficulty of science by "proceed[ing] so readily to frame a theory of such a general character" on limited evidence from their senses.[221] In 1985, the biologist Peter Medawar could still state in "pure seventeenth century"[222] tones that Aristotle had assembled "a strange and generally speaking rather tiresome farrago of hearsay, imperfect observation, wishful thinking and credulity amounting to downright gullibility".[222][223]
Zoologists have frequently mocked Aristotle for errors and unverified secondhand reports. However, modern observation has confirmed several of his more surprising claims.
Depictions in art
Paintings
Aristotle has been depicted by major artists including Lucas Cranach the Elder,[237] Justus van Gent, Raphael, Paolo Veronese, Jusepe de Ribera,[238] Rembrandt,[239] and Francesco Hayez over the centuries. Among the best-known depictions is Raphael's fresco The School of Athens, in the Vatican's Apostolic Palace, where the figures of Plato and Aristotle are central to the image, at the architectural vanishing point, reflecting their importance.[240] Rembrandt's Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, too, is a celebrated work, showing the knowing philosopher and the blind Homer from an earlier age: as the art critic Jonathan Jones writes, "this painting will remain one of the greatest and most mysterious in the world, ensnaring us in its musty, glowing, pitch-black, terrible knowledge of time."[241][242]
-
Aristotle, mosaic from a Roman villa in Cologne
-
anachronisticallyshows Aristotle in a medieval scholar's clothing. Ink and watercolour on paper, 1493
-
Aristotle by Justus van Gent. Oil on panel, c. 1476
-
Phyllis and Aristotle by Lucas Cranach the Elder. Oil on panel, 1530
-
Aristotle by Paolo Veronese, Biblioteka Marciana. Oil on canvas, 1560s
-
Aristotle by Jusepe de Ribera. Oil on canvas, 1637
-
Aristotle by Johann Jakob Dorner the Elder. Oil on canvas, 1813
-
Aristotle by Francesco Hayez. Oil on canvas, 1811
-
By Charles Laplante "That most enduring of romantic images, Aristotle tutoring the future conqueror Alexander".[168] 1866
Sculptures
-
Roman copy of 1st or 2nd century from original bronze byLouvre Museum
-
Roman copy of 117–138 AD of Greek original. Palermo Regional Archeology Museum
-
Relief of Aristotle and Plato by Luca della Robbia, Florence Cathedral, 1437–1439
-
Stone statue in niche, Gladstone's Library, Hawarden, Wales, 1899
-
Bronze statue, University of Freiburg, Germany, 1915
Eponyms
The
See also
References
Notes
- ^ /ˈærɪstɒtəl/ ⓘ ARR-ih-stot-əl[1]
- ^ pronounced [aristotélɛːs]
- Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, which in turn borrows material from earlier, now mostly lost, sources. Düring 1957covers ancient biographies of Aristotle.
- FGrHist244 F 38. Ingemar Düring, Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition, Göteborg, 1957, p. 253
- ^ Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73 write that Hermias died in 345 BC; Hazel 2013, p. 37 places Hermias' death in 342 BC, the same year as Aristotle's trip back to Macedon, while Nawotka 2009, p. 40 mentions that Hermias got arrested in 341 BC.
- Barbara.[53]
- ^ M is the Middle (here, Men), S is the Subject (Greeks), P is the Predicate (mortal).[53]
- ^ The first equation can be read as 'It is not true that there exists an x such that x is a man and that x is not mortal.'[54]
- Newton's First Law is "essentially a direct reply to Aristotle, that the natural state is not to change motion.[65]
- ^ Leonard Susskind comments that Aristotle had clearly never gone ice skating or he would have seen that it takes force to stop an object.[67]
- ^ For heavenly bodies like the Sun, Moon, and stars, the observed motions are "to a very good approximation" circular around the Earth's centre, (for example, the apparent rotation of the sky because of the rotation of the Earth, and the rotation of the moon around the Earth) as Aristotle stated.[68]
- ^ Drabkin quotes numerous passages from Physics and On the Heavens (De Caelo) which state Aristotle's laws of motion.[66]
- ^ Drabkin agrees that density is treated quantitatively in this passage, but without a sharp definition of density as weight per unit volume.[66]
- ^ Philoponus and Galileo correctly objected that for the transient phase (still increasing in speed) with heavy objects falling a short distance, the law does not apply: Galileo used balls on a short incline to show this. Rovelli notes that "Two heavy balls with the same shape and different weight do fall at different speeds from an aeroplane, confirming Aristotle's theory, not Galileo's."[68]
- ^ For a different reading of social and economic processes in the Nicomachean Ethics and Politics see Polanyi, Karl (1957) "Aristotle Discovers the Economy" in Primitive, Archaic and Modern Economies: Essays of Karl Polanyi ed. G. Dalton, Boston 1971, 78–115.
- ^ Compare the medieval tale of Phyllis and Alexander above.
Citations
- ^ Collins English Dictionary.
- ^ Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 3; Shields 2012, p. 3; Blits 1999, p. 58; Aristotle (Greek philosopher)
- ^ McLeisch 1999, p. 5; Hazel 2013, p. 36
- ^ Aristoteles-Park in Stagira.
- ^ Ogden 2024, p. 32; Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 3; Shields 2012, p. 5; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 36; Nawotka 2009, p. 40
- ^ Anagnostopoulos 2013, pp. 4; Shields 2012, p. 5; Hazel 2013, pp. 36–37; Reeve & Miller 2015, p. 250
- ^ Anagnostopoulos 2013, pp. 4–5; Shields 2012, p. 5; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Lloyd, Brunschwig & Pellegrin 2000, p. 554
- ^ Lloyd, Brunschwig & Pellegrin 2000, pp. 554–555; Hall 2018, p. 40
- ^ Hall 2018, p. 14; Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 4; Shields 2012, p. 5
- ^ Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 4; Hazel 2013, p. 37; Shields 2012, p. 5
- ^ Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Blits 1999, p. 58
- ^ Hazel 2013, p. 37.
- ^ Evans 2006, p. 18.
- ^ Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37
- ^ a b Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73.
- ^ Aristotle 1984, pp. Introduction.
- ^ Shields 2012, p. 6; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37
- ^ Shields 2012, p. 6.
- ^ Wu 2022, p. 71; Worthington 2014b, pp. 69–70; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Shields 2012, pp. 6–7; Nawotka 2009, p. 39; Green 1991, p. 54
- ^ Ogden 2024, p. 32; Shields 2012, p. 5; Nawotka 2009, pp. 39–40; Lloyd, Brunschwig & Pellegrin 2000, p. 555
- ^ Ogden 2024, p. 32; Worthington 2014a, p. 34; Shields 2012, p. 7; Nawotka 2009, p. 39
- ^ Wu 2022, p. 71; Nawotka 2009, p. 40
- ^ Hornblower 2002, p. 91; Hazel 2013, p. 37
- ^ Worthington 2014a, pp. 34–35; Nawotka 2009, pp. 41–42; Green 1991, pp. 58–59
- ^ Green 1991, pp. 58–59; Worthington 2014b, p. 96
- ^ Worthington 2014b, p. 97; Hazel 2013, p. 37
- ^ Ogden 2024, p. 32; Worthington 2014b, pp. 97, 186; Nawotka 2009, p. 40
- ^ Ogden 2024, p. 32; Hazel 2013, p. 37 provides the alternative translations On Monarchy and Colonists
- ^ Shields 2012, p. 7.
- ^ Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37; Shields 2012, p. 7
- ^ Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37
- ^ Shields 2012, p. 7; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73; Hazel 2013, p. 37
- ^ Shields 2012, p. 7; Hazel 2013, p. 37
- ^ Shields 2012, p. 7; Russell 1972
- ^ a b c Humphreys 2009.
- ^ Wu 2022, pp. 72–74.
- ^ Green 1991, p. 460.
- ^ Filonik 2013, pp. 72–73.
- ^ Jones 1980, p. 216; Gigon 2017, p. 41; Düring 1957, p. T44a-e
- ^ a b Aristotle (Greek philosopher).
- ^ Britton, Bianca (27 May 2016). "Is this Aristotle's tomb?". CNN. Retrieved 21 January 2023.
- ^ Haase 1992, p. 3862.
- ^ Hazel 2013, p. 38; Nussbaum & Osborne 2014, p. 73
- ^ Degnan 1994, pp. 81–89.
- ^ Corcoran 2009, pp. 1–20.
- ^ Kant 1787, pp. Preface.
- ^ School of Athens.
- ^ Stewart 2019.
- ^ Pickover 2009, p. 52.
- ^ Prior Analytics, pp. 24b18–20.
- ^ Bobzien 2015.
- ^ a b c Smith 2017.
- ^ a b c d Lagerlund 2016.
- ^ Predicate Logic.
- ^ Evans, John David Gemmill (1977). Aristotle's concept of dialectic. Cambridge University Press. pp. 86–87.
- ISSN 0144-5340.
- ^ a b c d e f g Cohen 2000.
- ^ Aristotle 1999, p. 111.
- ^ Metaphysics, pp. VIII 1043a 10–30.
- ^ Lloyd 1968, pp. 43–47.
- ^ Metaphysics, p. IX 1050a 5–10.
- ^ Metaphysics, p. VIII 1045a–b.
- ^ a b c d Wildberg 2016.
- ^ a b Lloyd 1968, pp. 133–139, 166–169.
- ^ a b Allain 2016.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i Drabkin 1938, pp. 60–84.
- ^ a b c d e Susskind 2011.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i Rovelli 2015, pp. 23–40.
- ^ Carteron 1923, pp. 1–32 and passim.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 88–90.
- ^ a b c d e Lloyd 1996, pp. 96–100, 106–107.
- ^ Hankinson 1998, p. 159.
- ^ a b Leroi 2015, pp. 91–92, 369–373.
- ^ Burnyeat, Myles F. "Archytas and optics". Science in Context 18.1 (2005): pp. 35-53.
- .
- ^ Cantor, Geoffrey N. "Physical optics". Companion to the History of Modern Science. Routledge, 2006. pp. 627–638.
- ^ Matthen, Mohan. "Is the eye like what it sees? A critique of Aristotle on sensing by assimilation". Vivarium 57.3-4 (2019): pp. 268–292.
- ^ Physics, p. 2.6.
- ^ Miller 1973, pp. 204–213.
- ^ Meteorology, p. 1. 8.
- ^ Meteorology.
- ^ Moore 1956, p. 13.
- ^ Meteorology, p. Book 1, Part 14.
- ^ Lyell 1832, p. 17.
- ^ Udias, Agustin; Buforn, Elisa (2018). Principles of Seismology. Cambridge University Press. p. 1.
- ^ Aristotle (1952). Meteorologica, Chapter II. Translated by Lee, H. D. P. (Loeb Classical Library ed.). Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. p. 156. Retrieved 22 January 2021.
- ^ Leroi 2015, p. 7.
- ^ Leroi 2015, p. 14.
- ^ Thompson 1910, p. Prefatory Note.
- ^ "Darwin's Ghosts, By Rebecca Stott". The Independent (UK). 2 June 2012. Retrieved 19 June 2012.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 196, 248.
- ^ Day 2013, pp. 5805–5816.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 66–74, 137.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 118–119.
- ^ Leroi 2015, p. 73.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 135–136.
- ^ Leroi 2015, p. 206.
- ^ Sedley 2007, p. 189.
- ^ Leroi 2015, p. 273.
- ^ Taylor 1922, p. 42.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 361–365.
- ^ Leroi 2011.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 197–200.
- ^ a b Leroi 2015, pp. 365–368.
- ^ Taylor 1922, p. 49.
- ^ Leroi 2015, p. 408.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 72–74.
- ^ Bergstrom & Dugatkin 2012, p. 35.
- ^ Rhodes 1974, p. 7.
- ^ Mayr 1982, pp. 201–202.
- ^ Lovejoy 1976.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 111–119.
- ISBN 0-521-65976-0.
- S2CID 210140121.
- ISSN 1791-6763.
- PMID 19203017.
- ISBN 978-1-00-091257-9.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 156–163.
- ^ a b Shields 2016.
- ^ Mason 1979, p. 45.
- ^ Guthrie 2010, p. 348.
- ^ On the Soul, I.3 406b26-407a10.
- ^ For instance, Ross, William D. ed. 1961. Aristotle: De Anima. Oxford: Oxford University Press, page 189.
- ^ On the Soul, I.3 407b14–27.
- ^ Bloch 2007, p. 12.
- ^ Bloch 2007, p. 61.
- ^ Carruthers 2007, p. 16.
- ^ Bloch 2007, p. 25.
- ^ Warren 1921, p. 30.
- ^ Warren 1921, p. 25.
- ^ Carruthers 2007, p. 19.
- ^ Warren 1921, p. 296.
- ^ Warren 1921, p. 259.
- ^ Sorabji 2006, p. 54.
- ^ a b c d e f Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–423.
- ^ a b c d e Shute 1941, pp. 115–118.
- ^ Holowchak 1996, pp. 405–23.
- ^ a b Modrak 2009, pp. 169–181.
- ^ Webb 1990, pp. 174–184.
- ^ Kraut 2001.
- ^ Nicomachean Ethics Book I. See for example chapter 7.
- ^ Nicomachean Ethics, Book VI.
- ^ Politics, pp. 1253a19–124.
- ^ Aristotle 2009, pp. 320–321.
- ^ Ebenstein & Ebenstein 2002, p. 59.
- ^ a b Hutchinson & Johnson 2015, p. 22.
- ^ a b c Robbins 2000, pp. 20–24.
- ^ a b c d Aristotle 1948, pp. 16–28.
- ^ Garver 1994, pp. 109–110.
- ^ Rorty 1996, pp. 3–7.
- ^ Grimaldi 1998, p. 71.
- ^ a b c d e Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–159.
- ^ Poetics, p. I 1447a.
- ^ Poetics, p. IV.
- ^ Halliwell 2002, pp. 152–59.
- ^ Poetics, p. III.
- ^ Kaufmann 1968, pp. 56–60.
- ^ Poetics, p. VI.
- ^ Poetics, p. XXVI.
- ^ Aesop 1998, pp. Introduction, xi–xii.
- ^ Leroi 2015, p. 8.
- ^ Aristotle's Influence 2018.
- ^ Garner., Dwight (14 March 2014). "Who's More Famous Than Jesus?". The New York Times. Archived from the original on 1 April 2021.
- ^ Magee 2010, p. 34.
- JSTOR 24591937.
- ISSN 0028-0836.
- ^ Durant 2006, p. 92.
- ^ a b c d Kukkonen 2010, pp. 70–77.
- ^ Barnes 1982, p. 86.
- ^ a b Leroi 2015, p. 352.
- ^ * "the father of logic": Wentzel Van Huyssteen, Encyclopedia of Science and Religion: A–I, p. 27
- "the father of biology": S. C. Datt, S. B. Srivastava, Science and society, p. 93.[170]
- "the father of political science": N. Jayapalan, Aristotle, p. 12, Jonathan Wolff, Lectures on the History of Moral and Political Philosophy, p. 48.
- the "father of zoology": Josef Rudolf Winkler, A Book of Beetles, p. 12
- "the father of embryology": D. R. Khanna, Text Book Of Embryology, p. 2
- "the father of natural law": Shellens, Max Solomon (1959). "Aristotle on Natural Law". Natural Law Forum. 4 (1): 72–100. ISSN 0065-8995.
- "the father of scientific method": Shuttleworth, Martyn. "History of the Scientific Method". Explorable., Riccardo Pozzo (2004) The impact of Aristotelianism on modern philosophy. CUA Press. p. 41. ISBN 0-8132-1347-9
- "the father of psychology": Margot Esther Borden, Psychology in the Light of the East, p. 4
- "the father of realism": Russell L. Hamm, Philosophy and Education: Alternatives in Theory and Practice, p. 58
- "the father of criticism": Nagendra Prasad, Personal Bias in Literary Criticism: Johnson, Matthew Arnold, T. S. Eliot, p. 70. Lord Henry Home Kames, Elements of Criticism, p. 237.
- "the father of meteorology":"What is meteorology?". Meteorological Office."94.05.01: Meteorology". Archived from the original on 21 July 2016. Retrieved 16 June 2015.
- "the father of individualism": Allan Gotthelf, Gregory Salmieri, A Companion to Ayn Rand, p. 325.
- "the father of teleology": Malcolm Owen Slavin, Daniel H. Kriegman, The Adaptive Design of the Human Psyche: Psychoanalysis, Evolutionary Biology, and the Therapeutic Process, p. 292.
- ^ a b Russell 1972, Chapter 19 "Aristotle's Metaphysics".
- ^ Wilkins 2009, p. 15.
- ^ Ostwald & Lynch 1982, pp. 623–624.
- ^ Hooker 1831, p. 219.
- ^ Mayr 1982, pp. 90–91.
- ^ Mason 1979, p. 46.
- ^ Mason 1979, p. 56.
- ^ Barnes 1995, p. 12.
- ^ House 1956, p. 35.
- ^ Barnes 1995, p. 9.
- ^ Anagnostopoulos 2013, p. 16.
- ^ Barnes 1995, pp. 10–15.
- ^ a b Falcon 2021.
- ^ Ahbel-Rappe 2010, p. 424 (note 17), Notes to Pages 4-7.
- ^ Sorabji 1990.
- ^ Sorabji 1990, pp. 233–724.
- ^ Lindberg 1992, p. 162.
- ^ Sorabji 1990, pp. 20–21, 28–29, 393–406, 407–408.
- ^ Ierodiakonou 2008.
- .
- ISBN 978-0-415-06133-9.
- ^ Admin (13 February 2017). "The Reception of Aristotelian Science in Early Islam: A Historical Account". Interdisciplinary Humanities Center UCSB. Retrieved 27 January 2024.
- ISBN 978-1-107-10173-9.
- ^ a b Kennedy-Day 1998.
- ^ Staley 1989.
- ^ Averroes 1953, p. III, 2, 43.
- ISBN 978-0-231-05533-8.
- ^ Nasr 1996, pp. 59–60.
- ^ "Moses Maimonides". Britannica. 26 March 2023.
- ^ Levi ben Gershom, The Wars of the Lord: Book one, Immortality of the soul, p. 35.
- ^ Leon Simon, Aspects Of The Hebrew Genius: A Volume Of Essays On Jewish Literature And Thought (1910), p. 127.
- ^ Herbert A. Davidson, Herbert A. |q (Herbert Alan) Davidson, Professor of Hebrew Emeritus Herbert Davidson, Moses Maimonides: The Man and His Works, p. 98.
- ^ Menachem Kellner, Maimonides on Judaism and the Jewish People, p. 77.
- ^ Hasse 2014.
- ^ "Medieval Chronology" (PDF). bc.edu. Archived from the original (PDF) on 17 September 2006. Retrieved 8 March 2007.
- ^ "Aristutalis" in Encyclopedia of Islam 2nd. ed. Brill, Leiden, Vol. 1 p. 631.
- ^ Aquinas 2013.
- ^ Kuhn 2018.
- ^ Lafferty, Roger. "The Philosophy of Dante", p. 4
- ^ Inferno, Canto XI, lines 70–115, Mandelbaum translation.
- ^ Inferno, Canto IV, lines 115-16 trans., 131 original, Robert Pinksky translation (1994); note to line, p.384
- ^ Kukkonen 2010, p. 74.
- ^ Aird 2011, pp. 118–29.
- ^ Machamer 2017.
- ^ Boole 2003.
- OCLC 314379168.
- OCLC 680621287.
- ^ Darwin 1872, p. xiii
- ^ Aristotle. "Physics". translated by Hardie, R. P. and Gayle, R. K. and hosted by MIT's Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 23 April 2009.
- ^ Dijksterhuis 1969, p. 72.
- ^ a b Leroi 2015, p. 353.
- ^ Medawar & Medawar 1984, p. 28.
- ISBN 978-0-674-07227-5.
- ISBN 978-0-300-12539-9.
- ^ Leroi 2015, pp. 137–138.
- ^ "A History of the Study of Marine Biology". MarineBio Conservation Society. Retrieved 19 November 2016.
- ISSN 1936-6434.
- ^ Leroi 2015.
- ^ MacDougall-Shackleton 2011, pp. 2076–2085.
- ^ Hladký & Havlíček 2013.
- PMID 10332750.
- ISBN 978-1-316-60121-1.
- S2CID 55152069.
- ISSN 1467-2960.
- S2CID 245863171.
- ^ Lucas Cranach the Elder.
- ^ Lee & Robinson 2005.
- ^ Aristotle with Bust 2002.
- ^ Phelan 2002.
- ^ Held 1969.
- ^ Jones 2002.
- ^ Aristotle Mountains.
- ^ Aristoteles.
- ^ "IAU Minor Planet Center". minorplanetcenter.net. Retrieved 1 July 2024.
Sources
- Damascius' Problems and Solutions Concerning First Principles (in English and Ancient Greek). Translated by Ahbel-Rappe, Sara. New York: Oxford University Press, Inc. 2010. ISBN 9780195150292.
- ISBN 978-0-14-044649-4.
- Aird, W. C. (2011). "Discovery of the cardiovascular system: from Galen to William Harvey". Journal of Thrombosis and Haemostasis. 9: 118–129. S2CID 12092592.
- Allain, Rhett (21 March 2016). "I'm So Totally Over Newton's Laws of Motion". Wired. Retrieved 11 May 2018.
- Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (2013). A Companion to Aristotle. Wiley. ISBN 978-1-118-59243-4.
- ISBN 978-80-7484-292-4.
- Aristoteles (31 January 2019) [1831]. Bekker, Immanuel (ed.). "Aristotelis Opera edidit Academia Regia Borussica Aristoteles graece". apud Georgium Reimerum. Retrieved 31 January 2019 – via Internet Archive.
- "Aristoteles". Gazetteer of Planetary Nomenclature. United States Geological Survey. Retrieved 19 March 2018.
- "Aristoteles-Park in Stagira". Dimos Aristoteli. Retrieved 20 March 2018.
- "Aristotle (Greek philosopher)". Encyclopædia Britannica. Britannica Online Encyclopedia. Archived from the original on 22 April 2009. Retrieved 26 April 2009.
- Aristotle. "Metaphysics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
- Aristotle. "Meteorology". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
- Aristotle. "Nicomachean Ethics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive.
- Aristotle. "On the Soul". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
- Aristotle. "Physics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 31 January 2019.
- Aristotle. "Poetics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
- Aristotle. "Politics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive. Retrieved 30 January 2019.
- Aristotle. "Prior Analytics". classics.mit.edu. The Internet Classics Archive.
- Aristotle. "Rhetoric". Translated by Roberts, W. Rhys. Archived from the original on 13 February 2015.
- "Aristotle Mountains". Programma Nazionale di Ricerche in Antartide. Department of the Environment and Energy, Australian Antarctic Division, Australian Government. Retrieved 1 March 2018.
- Aristotle (1948). Monroe, Arthur E. (ed.). Politics-Ethics, In Early Economic Thought: Selections from Economic Literature Prior to Adam Smith. Harvard University Press.
- Aristotle (1984). Lord, Carnes (ed.). The Politics. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-92184-6.
- Aristotle (2009) [1995]. Politics. Translated by Ernest Barker and revised with introduction and notes by R. F. Stalley (1st ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953873-7.
- Aristotle (1999). Aristotle's Metaphysics. Translated by Sachs, Joe. Green Lion Press.
- "Aristotle definition and meaning". www.collinsdictionary.com. Collins English Dictionary.
- "Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653)". The Guardian. 27 July 2002. Retrieved 23 March 2018.
- Averroes (1953). Crawford, F. Stuart (ed.). Commentarium Magnum in Aristotelis De Anima Libros. Mediaeval Academy of America. OCLC 611422373.
- ISBN 978-0-19-285408-7.
- ISBN 978-0-521-42294-9.
- ISBN 978-0-19-815222-4.
- Bergstrom, Carl T.; Dugatkin, Lee Alan (2012). Evolution. Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-92592-0.
- Blits, Kathleen C. (15 April 1999). "Aristotle: Form, function, and comparative anatomy". The Anatomical Record. 257 (2): 58–63. PMID 10321433.
- Bloch, David (2007). Aristotle on Memory and Recollection. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-16046-0.
- Bobzien, Susanne (2015). "Ancient Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ISBN 978-1-59102-089-9.
- ISBN 978-0-521-42973-3.
- Carteron, Henri (1923). Notion de Force dans le Systeme d'Aristote (in French). J. Vrin.
- Cicero, Marcus Tullius (1874). "Book II, chapter XXXVIII, § 119". In Reid, James S. (ed.). The Academica of Cicero 106–43 BC. Macmillan.
- Cohen, S. Marc (8 October 2000). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Retrieved 14 November 2018.
- Corcoran, John (2009). "Aristotle's Demonstrative Logic". History and Philosophy of Logic. 30: 1–20. S2CID 8514675.
- Darwin, Charles (1872). The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life (6th ed.). London: John Murray. Retrieved 9 January 2009.
- Day, J. (2013). "Botany meets archaeology: people and plants in the past". Journal of Experimental Botany. 64 (18): 5805–5816. PMID 23669575.
- Degnan, Michael (1994). "Recent Work in Aristotle's Logic". Philosophical Books. 35 (2 (April 1994)): 81–89. .
- Dijksterhuis, Eduard Jan (1969). The Mechanization of the World Picture. Translated by C. Dikshoorn. Princeton University Press.
- JSTOR 90584.
- ISBN 978-0-671-73916-4.
- Düring, Ingemar (1957). Aristotle in the Ancient Biographical Tradition. By Ingemar Düring. Almqvist & Wiksell in Komm.
- Ebenstein, Alan; Ebenstein, William (2002). Introduction to Political Thinkers. Wadsworth Group.
- Evans, Nancy (2006). "Diotima and Demeter as Mystagogues in Plato's Symposium". Hypatia. 21 (2): 1–27. S2CID 143750010.
- Zalta, Edward N., ed. (2021). "Commentators on Aristotle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Filonik, Jakub (2013). "Athenian impiety trials: a reappraisal". Dike. 16 (16): 72–73. .
- Garver, Eugene (1994). Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-28425-5.
- Gigon, Olof (2017) [1965]. Vita Aristotelis Marciana. Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-082017-1.
- Green, Peter (1991). Alexander of Macedon. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-27586-7.
- Grimaldi, William M. A. (1998). "Studies in the Philosophy of Aristotle's Rhetoric". In Enos, Richard Leo; Agnew, Lois Peters (eds.). Landmark Essays on Aristotelian Rhetoric. Vol. 14. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. p. 71. ISBN 978-1-880393-32-1.
- Guthrie, W. (2010). A History of Greek Philosophy Vol. 1. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-29420-1.
- Haase, Wolfgang (1992). Philosophie, Wissenschaften, Technik. Philosophie (Doxographica [Forts. ]) (in German). Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-013699-9.
- ISBN 978-1-84792-407-0.
- ISBN 978-0-691-09258-4.
- Hankinson, R. J. (1998). Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-823745-7.
- Hasse, Dag Nikolaus (2014). "Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Hazel, John (2013) [1999]. Who's Who in the Greek World. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-134-80223-4.
- ISBN 978-0-691-03862-9.
- Hladký, V.; Havlíček, J. (2013). "Was Tinbergen an Aristotelian? Comparison of Tinbergen's Four Whys and Aristotle's Four Causes" (PDF). Human Ethology Bulletin. 28 (4): 3–11.
- Holowchak, Mark (1996). "Aristotle on Dreaming: What Goes on in Sleep when the 'Big Fire' goes out". Ancient Philosophy. 16 (2): 405–423. .
- OCLC 17317293.
- House, Humphry (1956). Aristotle's Poetics. Rupert Hart-Davis.
- Hornblower, Simon (2002). The Greek World, 479–323 BC. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-16326-9.
- Humphreys, Justin (2009). "Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Hutchinson, D. S.; Johnson, Monte Ransome (2015). "Exhortation to Philosophy" (PDF). Protrepticus. p. 22.
- Zalta, Edward N., ed. (2008). "Byzantine Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Irwin, Terence; ISBN 978-0-87220-339-6.
- Jones, Jonathan (27 July 2002). "Aristotle with a Bust of Homer, Rembrandt (1653)". The Guardian. Retrieved 23 March 2018.
- Jones, W. T. (1980). The Classical Mind: A History of Western Philosophy. Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. ISBN 978-0-15-538312-8.
- OCLC 2323615.
- Kaufmann, Walter Arnold (1968). Tragedy and Philosophy. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02005-1.
- Kennedy-Day, Kiki (1998). "Aristotelianism in Islamic philosophy". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Taylor and Francis. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6.
- Kraut, Richard (1 May 2001). "Aristotle's Ethics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 March 2018.
- Kuhn, Heinrich (2018). "Aristotelianism in the Renaissance". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Kukkonen, Taneli (2010). Grafton, Anthony; et al. (eds.). The classical tradition. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0.
- Lagerlund, Henrik (2016). "Medieval Theories of the Syllogism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Lee, Ellen Wardwell; Robinson, Anne (2005). Indianapolis Museum of Art: Highlights of the Collection. ISBN 978-0-936260-77-8.
- Leroi, Armand Marie (3 May 2011). "Aristotle's Lagoon: Embryo Inside a Chicken's Egg". BBC. Retrieved 17 November 2016.
- ISBN 978-1-4088-3622-4.
- Lindberg, David (1992). The Beginnings of Western Science. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-48205-7.
- ISBN 978-0-521-09456-6.
- ISBN 978-0-521-55695-8.
- Lloyd, E. R. G.; Brunschwig, Jacques; Pellegrin, Pierre (2000). Greek Thought, A Guide to Classical Knowledge. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-00261-6.
- ISBN 978-0-674-36153-9.
- "Lucas Cranach the Elder| Phyllis and Aristotle". Sotheby's. 2008. Retrieved 23 March 2018.
- OCLC 609586345.
- MacDougall-Shackleton, Scott A. (27 July 2011). "The levels of analysis revisited". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. 366 (1574): 2076–2085. PMID 21690126.
- Machamer, Peter (2017). "Galileo Galilei". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ISBN 978-0-241-24126-4.
- Mason, Stephen F. (1979). A History of the Sciences. Collier Books. OCLC 924760574.
- ISBN 978-0-674-36446-2.
- ISBN 978-0-674-36446-2.
- McLeisch, Kenneth Cole (1999). Aristotle: The Great Philosophers. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-92392-7.
- ISBN 978-0-19-283043-2.
- Miller, Willard M. (1973). "Aristotle on Necessity, Chance, and Spontaneity". New Scholasticism. 47 (2): 204–213. .
- Modrak, Deborah (2009). "Dreams and Method in Aristotle". Skepsis: A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research. 20: 169–181.
- Moore, Ruth (1956). The Earth We Live On. Alfred A. Knopf. OCLC 1024467091.
- Nasr, Seyyed Hossein (1996). The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia. Curzon Press. ISBN 978-0-7007-0314-2.
- Nawotka, Krzysztof (2009). Alexander the Great. Cambridge Scholars Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4438-1811-7.
- ISBN 978-0-19-954556-8.
- Ogden, Daniel (2024). The Cambridge Companion to Alexander the Great. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-84099-6.
- Ostwald, M.; Lynch, J. (1982). "The Growth of Schools & the Advance of Knowledge". In Lewis, D. M.; Boardman, John; Hornblower, Simon; et al. (eds.). The Cambridge Ancient History Volume 6: The Fourth Century BCE. Cambridge University Press.
- Phelan, Joseph (September 2002). "The Philosopher as Hero: Raphael's The School of Athens". ArtCyclopedia. Retrieved 23 March 2018.
- ISBN 978-1-4027-5796-9.
- "Plutarch – Life of Alexander (Part 1 of 7)". penelope.uchicago.edu. Loeb Classical Library. 1919. Retrieved 31 January 2019.
- "Predicate Logic" (PDF). University of Texas. Archived (PDF) from the original on 29 March 2018. Retrieved 29 March 2018.
- Reeve, C. D. C.; Miller, Patrick L. (2015) [2006]. Introductory Readings in Ancient Greek and Roman Philosophy. Hackett. ISBN 978-1-62466-354-3.
- Rhodes, Frank Harold Trevor (1974). Evolution. Golden Press. ISBN 978-0-307-64360-5.
- Robbins, Lionel (2000). Medema, Steven G.; Samuels, Warren J. (eds.). A History of Economic Thought: The LSE Lectures. Princeton University Press.
- ISBN 978-0-520-20227-6.
- S2CID 44193681.
- Russell, Bertrand (1972). A history of western philosophy. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-671-31400-2.
- Sedley, David (2007). Creationism and Its Critics in Antiquity. University of California Press. ISBN 978-0-520-25364-3.
- Shields, Christopher (2012). The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-518748-9.
- Shields, Christopher (2016). "Aristotle's Psychology". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.).
- Shute, Clarence (1941). The Psychology of Aristotle: An Analysis of the Living Being. Columbia University Press. OCLC 936606202.
- Smith, Robin (2017). "Aristotle's Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Sorabji, R. (2006). Aristotle on Memory (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. p. 54.
And this is exactly why we hunt for the successor, starting in our thoughts from the present or from something else, and from something similar, or opposite, or neighbouring. By this means recollection occurs...
- ISBN 978-0-7156-2254-4.
- Staley, Kevin (1989). "Al-Kindi on Creation: Aristotle's Challenge to Islam". Journal of the History of Ideas. 50 (3): 355–370. JSTOR 2709566.
- Susskind, Leonard (3 October 2011). "Classical Mechanics, Lectures 2, 3". The Theoretical Minimum. Retrieved 11 May 2018.
- Taylor, Henry Osborn (1922). "Chapter 3: Aristotle's Biology". Greek Biology and Medicine. Archived from the original on 27 March 2006. Retrieved 3 January 2017.
- "The School of Athens by Raphael". Visual Arts Cork. Retrieved 22 March 2018.
- Stewart, Jessica (2019). "The Story Behind Raphael's Masterpiece 'The School of Athens'". My Modern Met. Retrieved 29 March 2019.
Plato's gesture toward the sky is thought to indicate his Theory of Forms. ... Conversely, Aristotle's hand is a visual representation of his belief that knowledge comes from experience. Empiricism, as it is known, theorizes that humans must have concrete evidence to support their ideas
- OCLC 39273217. Archived from the originalon 9 August 2019. Retrieved 19 March 2018.
- ISBN 978-0-598-91975-5.)
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: ignored ISBN errors (link - Webb, Wilse (1990). Dreamtime and dreamwork: Decoding the language of the night. Jeremy P. Tarcher. ISBN 978-0-87477-594-5.
- "When libraries were on a roll". The Telegraph. 19 May 2001. Archived from the original on 10 January 2022. Retrieved 29 June 2017.
- Wildberg (2016). "John Philoponus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Worthington, Ian (2014a) [2004]. Alexander the Great: Man and God. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-317-86644-2.
- Worthington, Ian (2014b). By the Spear: Philip II, Alexander the Great, and the Rise and Fall of the Macedonian Empire. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-992986-3.
- Wu, Yuchen (2022). "The Relationship Between Aristotle and Alexander the Great". Proceedings of the 2021 International Conference on Public Art and Human Development (ICPAHD 2021). Proceedings of the 2021 International Conference on Public Art and Human Development ( ICPAHD 2021). Vol. 638. Paris, France: Atlantis Press. ISSN 2352-5398.
- Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Aristotle's Influence". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.).
Further reading
The secondary literature on Aristotle is vast. The following is only a small selection.
- Ackrill, J. L. (1997). Essays on Plato and Aristotle, Oxford University Press.
- Ackrill, J. L. (1981). Aristotle the Philosopher. Oxford University Press.
- Adler, Mortimer J. (1978). Aristotle for Everybody. Macmillan.
- Ammonius (1991). Cohen, S. Marc; Matthews, Gareth B. (eds.). On Aristotle's Categories. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-2688-9.
- Aristotle (1908–1952). The Works of Aristotle Translated into English Under the Editorship of W. D. Ross, 12 vols. Clarendon Press. These translations are available in several places online; see External links.
- Bakalis, Nikolaos. (2005). Handbook of Greek Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis and Fragments, Trafford Publishing, ISBN 978-1-4120-4843-9.
- Bocheński, I. M. (1951). Ancient Formal Logic. North-Holland.
- Bolotin, David (1998). An Approach to Aristotle's Physics: With Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing. Albany: SUNY Press. A contribution to our understanding of how to read Aristotle's scientific works.
- Burnyeat, Myles F. et al. (1979). Notes on Book Zeta of Aristotle's Metaphysics. Oxford: Sub-faculty of Philosophy.
- Cantor, Norman F.; Klein, Peter L., eds. (1969). Ancient Thought: Plato and Aristotle. Monuments of Western Thought. Vol. 1. Blaisdell.
- Chappell, V. (1973). "Aristotle's Conception of Matter". Journal of Philosophy. 70 (19): 679–696. JSTOR 2025076.
- Code, Alan (1995). Potentiality in Aristotle's Science and Metaphysics, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76.
- Cohen, S. Marc; Reeve, C. D. C. (21 November 2020). "Aristotle's Metaphysics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.).
- Ferguson, John (1972). Aristotle. Twayne Publishers. ISBN 978-0-8057-2064-8.
- De Groot, Jean (2014). Aristotle's Empiricism: Experience and Mechanics in the 4th century BC, Parmenides Publishing, ISBN 978-1-930972-83-4.
- Frede, Michael (1987). Essays in Ancient Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
- Fuller, B. A. G. (1923). Aristotle. History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 3. Cape.
- Gendlin, Eugene T. (2012). Line by Line Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima Archived 27 March 2017 at the Wayback Machine, Volume 1: Books I & II; Volume 2: Book III. The Focusing Institute.
- Gill, Mary Louise (1989). Aristotle on Substance: The Paradox of Unity. Princeton University Press.
- Guthrie, W. K. C. (1981). A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 6. Cambridge University Press.
- Halper, Edward C. (2009). One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 1: Books Alpha – Delta. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-21-6.
- Halper, Edward C. (2005). One and Many in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Volume 2: The Central Books. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-05-6.
- ISBN 0-19-824290-5.
- Jaeger, Werner (1948). Robinson, Richard (ed.). Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development (2nd ed.). Clarendon Press.
- ISBN 978-88-424-9737-0.
- Kiernan, Thomas P., ed. (1962). Aristotle Dictionary. Philosophical Library.
- Knight, Kelvin (2007). Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre, Polity Press.
- Lewis, Frank A. (1991). Substance and Predication in Aristotle. Cambridge University Press.
- Lord, Carnes (1984). Introduction to The Politics, by Aristotle. Chicago University Press.
- Loux, Michael J. (1991). Primary Ousia: An Essay on Aristotle's Metaphysics Ζ and Η. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
- Maso, Stefano (Ed.), Natali, Carlo (Ed.), Seel, Gerhard (Ed.) (2012) Reading Aristotle: Physics VII. 3: What is Alteration? Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference, Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1-930972-73-5.
- McKeon, Richard (1973). Introduction to Aristotle (2nd ed.). University of Chicago Press.
- Owen, G. E. L. (1965c). "The Platonism of Aristotle". Proceedings of the British Academy. 50: 125–150. [Reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R. R. K. Sorabji, eds.(1975). Articles on Aristotle Vol 1. Science. London: Duckworth 14–34.]
- ISBN 978-0-511-49828-2.
- Plato (1979). Allen, Harold Joseph; Wilbur, James B. (eds.). The Worlds of Plato and Aristotle. Prometheus Books.
- Roreitner, Robert (2025). Aristotle on the Nature and Causes of Perception. ISBN 9781009533829.
- Rose, Lynn E. (1968). Aristotle's Syllogistic. Charles C. Thomas.
- Ross, David (1995). Aristotle (6th ed.). Routledge.
- Scaltsas, T. (1994). Substances and Universals in Aristotle's Metaphysics. Cornell University Press.
- Strauss, Leo (1964). "On Aristotle's Politics", in The City and Man, Rand McNally.
- Swanson, Judith (1992). The Public and the Private in Aristotle's Political Philosophy. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-2319-2.
- Veatch, Henry B.(1974). Aristotle: A Contemporary Appreciation. Indiana University Press.
- Woods, M. J. (1991b). "Universals and Particular Forms in Aristotle's Metaphysics". Aristotle and the Later Tradition. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy. Vol. Suppl. pp. 41–56.
External links
- Aristotle at PhilPapers
- 2553 Aristotle at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
- At the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
- At the Internet Classics Archive
- From the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
- Turner, William (1907). Catholic Encyclopedia. Vol. 1. .
- Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 1:5. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew(Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
- Collections of works
- Works by Aristotle in eBook form at Standard Ebooks
- At Massachusetts Institute of Technology
- Works by Aristotle at Project Gutenberg
- Works by or about Aristotle at the Internet Archive
- Works by Aristotle at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)
- Works by Aristotle at the Biodiversity Heritage Library
- Works by Aristotle at Open Library
- Perseus Project at Tufts University (in English and Greek)
- At the University of Adelaide
- P. Remacle (in Greek and French)
- The 11-volume 1837 Bekker edition of Aristotle's Works in Greek (PDF Archived 24 November 2022 at the Wayback Machine · DJVU)