Time
Time |
---|
![]() |
Time is the continuous progression of
Time is one of the seven fundamental
Throughout history, time has been an important subject of study in religion, philosophy, and science. Temporal measurement has occupied scientists and technologists, and has been a prime motivation in navigation and astronomy. Time is also of significant social importance, having economic value ("time is money") as well as personal value, due to an awareness of the limited time in each day ("carpe diem") and in human life spans.
Definition
The concept of time can be complex. Multiple notions exist, and defining time in a manner applicable to all fields without
In physics, time is a fundamental concept to define other quantities, such as
General relativity does not address the nature of time for extremely small intervals where quantum mechanics holds. In quantum mechanics, time is treated as a universal and absolute parameter, differing from general relativity's notion of independent clocks. The problem of time consists of reconciling these two theories.[20] As of 2025, there is no generally accepted theory of quantum general relativity.[21]
Measurement

Methods of temporal measurement, or chronometry, generally take two forms. The first is a calendar, a mathematical tool for organising intervals of time on Earth,[22] consulted for periods longer than a day. The second is a clock, a physical mechanism that indicates the passage of time, consulted for periods less than a day. The combined measurement marks a specific moment in time from a reference point, or epoch.
History of the calendar
Artifacts from the
Other early forms of calendars originated in
The reforms of Julius Caesar in 45 BC put the Roman world on a solar calendar. This Julian calendar was faulty in that its intercalation still allowed the astronomical solstices and equinoxes to advance against it by about 11 minutes per year. Pope Gregory XIII introduced a correction in 1582; the Gregorian calendar was only slowly adopted by different nations over a period of centuries, but it is now by far the most commonly used calendar around the world.
During the
History of other devices


A large variety of
A sundial is any device that uses the direction of sunlight to cast shadows from a gnomon onto a set of markings calibrated to indicate the local time, usually to the hour. The idea to separate the day into smaller parts is credited to Egyptians because of their sundials, which operated on a duodecimal system. The importance of the number 12 is due to the number of lunar cycles in a year and the number of stars used to count the passage of night.[28] Obelisks made as a gnomon were built as early as c. 3500 BC.[29] An Egyptian device that dates to c. 1500 BC, similar in shape to a bent T-square, also measured the passage of time from the shadow cast by its crossbar on a nonlinear rule. The T was oriented eastward in the mornings. At noon, the device was turned around so that it could cast its shadow in the evening direction.[30]
Alarm clocks reportedly first appeared in ancient Greece c. 250 BC with a water clock made by Plato that would set off a whistle.[31] The hydraulic alarm worked by gradually filling a series of vessels with water. After some time, the water emptied out of a siphon.[32] Inventor Ctesibius revised Plato's design; the water clock uses a float as the power drive system and uses a sundial to correct the water flow rate.[33]
In medieval philosophical writings, the atom was a unit of time referred to as the smallest possible division of time. The earliest known occurrence in English is in
Incense sticks and candles were, and are, commonly used to measure time in temples and churches across the globe. Water clocks, and, later, mechanical clocks, were used to mark the events of the abbeys and monasteries of the Middle Ages. The passage of the hours at sea can also be marked by
Great advances in accurate time-keeping were made by Galileo Galilei and especially Christiaan Huygens with the invention of pendulum-driven clocks along with the invention of the minute hand by Jost Burgi.[40] There is also a clock that was designed to keep time for 10,000 years called the Clock of the Long Now. Alarm clock devices were later mechanized. Levi Hutchins's alarm clock has been credited as the first American alarm clock, though it can only ring at 4 a.m. Antoine Redier was also credited as the first person to patent an adjustable mechanical alarm clock in 1847.[41] Digital forms of alarm clocks became more accessible through digitization and integration with other technologies, such as smartphones.

The most accurate timekeeping devices are
In modern times, the
Units
The second (s) is the
Time standards
A time standard is a specification for measuring time: assigning a number or calendar date to an instant (point in time), quantifying the duration of a time interval, and establishing a chronology (ordering of events). In modern times, several time specifications have been officially recognized as standards, where formerly they were matters of custom and practice. The invention in 1955 of the caesium atomic clock has led to the replacement of older and purely astronomical time standards such as sidereal time and ephemeris time, for most practical purposes, by newer time standards based wholly or partly on atomic time using the SI second.
International Atomic Time (TAI) is the primary international time standard from which other time standards are calculated. Universal Time (UT1) is mean solar time at 0° longitude, computed from astronomical observations. It varies from TAI because of the irregularities in Earth's rotation. Coordinated Universal Time (UTC) is an atomic time scale designed to approximate Universal Time. UTC differs from TAI by an integral number of seconds. UTC is kept within 0.9 second of UT1 by the introduction of one-second steps to UTC, the leap second. The Global Positioning System broadcasts a very precise time signal based on UTC time.
The surface of the Earth is split into a number of time zones. Standard time or civil time in a time zone deviates a fixed, round amount, usually a whole number of hours, from some form of Universal Time, usually UTC. Most time zones are exactly one hour apart, and by convention compute their local time as an offset from UTC. For example, time zones at sea are based on UTC. In many locations (but not at sea) these offsets vary twice yearly due to daylight saving time transitions.
Some other time standards are used mainly for scientific work. Terrestrial Time is a theoretical ideal scale realized by TAI. Geocentric Coordinate Time and Barycentric Coordinate Time are scales defined as coordinate times in the context of the general theory of relativity, with TCG applying to Earth's center and TCB to the solar system's barycenter. Barycentric Dynamical Time is an older relativistic scale related to TCB that is still in use.
Philosophy
Religion
Cyclical views of time
Many ancient cultures, particularly in the East, had a cyclical view of time. In these traditions, time was often seen as a recurring pattern of ages or cycles, where events and phenomena repeated themselves in a predictable manner. One of the most famous examples of this concept is found in Hindu philosophy, where time is depicted as a wheel called the "Kalachakra" or "Wheel of Time." According to this belief, the universe undergoes endless cycles of creation, preservation, and destruction.[47]
Similarly, in other ancient cultures such as those of the Mayans, Aztecs, and Chinese, there were also beliefs in cyclical time, often associated with astronomical observations and calendars.[48] These cultures developed complex systems to track time, seasons, and celestial movements, reflecting their understanding of cyclical patterns in nature and the universe.
The cyclical view of time contrasts with the linear concept of time more common in Western thought, where time is seen as progressing in a straight line from past to future without repetition.[49]
Time in Abrahamic religions
In general, the Islamic and Judeo-Christian world-view regards time as linear[50] and directional,[51] beginning with the act of creation by God. The traditional Christian view sees time ending, teleologically,[52] with the eschatological end of the present order of things, the "end time". Though some Christian theologians (such as Augustine of Hippo and Aquinas[53]) believe that God is outside of time, seeing all events simultaneously, that time did not exist before God, and that God created time.[54][55]
In the Old Testament book Ecclesiastes, traditionally ascribed to Solomon (970–928 BC), time is depicted as cyclical and beyond human control.[56] The book wrote that there is an appropriate season or time for every activity.[57]
Time in Greek mythology
The Greek language denotes two distinct principles, Chronos and Kairos. The former refers to numeric, or chronological, time. The latter, literally "the right or opportune moment", relates specifically to metaphysical or Divine time. In theology, Kairos is qualitative, as opposed to quantitative.[58]
In Greek mythology, Chronos (ancient Greek: Χρόνος) is identified as the personification of time. His name in Greek means "time" and is alternatively spelled Chronus (Latin spelling) or Khronos. Chronos is usually portrayed as an old, wise man with a long, gray beard, such as "Father Time". Some English words whose etymological root is khronos/chronos include chronology, chronometer, chronic, anachronism, synchronise, and chronicle.
Time in Kabbalah & Rabbinical thought
Rabbis sometimes saw time like "an accordion that was expanded and collapsed at will."[59] According to Kabbalists, "time" is a paradox[60] and an illusion.[61]
Time in Advaita Vedanta
According to Advaita Vedanta, time is integral to the phenomenal world, which lacks independent reality. Time and the phenomenal world are products of maya, influenced by our senses, concepts, and imaginations. The phenomenal world, including time, is seen as impermanent and characterized by plurality, suffering, conflict, and division. Since phenomenal existence is dominated by temporality (kala), everything within time is subject to change and decay. Overcoming pain and death requires knowledge that transcends temporal existence and reveals its eternal foundation.[62]
In Western philosophy
Two contrasting viewpoints on time divide prominent philosophers. One view is that time is part of the fundamental structure of the universe—a dimension independent of events, in which events occur in sequence. Isaac Newton subscribed to this realist view, and hence it is sometimes referred to as Newtonian time.[63][64]
The opposing view is that time does not refer to any kind of "container" that events and objects "move through", nor to any entity that "flows", but that it is instead part of a fundamental intellectual structure (together with
In philosophy, time was questioned throughout the centuries; what time is and if it is real or not. Ancient Greek philosophers asked if time was linear or cyclical and if time was endless or
The
Philosophers in the 17th and 18th century questioned if time was real and absolute, or if it was an intellectual concept that humans use to understand and sequence events.
Time is not an empirical concept. For neither co-existence nor succession would be perceived by us, if the representation of time did not exist as a foundation a priori. Without this presupposition, we could not represent to ourselves that things exist together at one and the same time, or at different times, that is, contemporaneously, or in succession.
Henri Bergson believed that time was neither a real homogeneous medium nor a mental construct, but possesses what he referred to as Duration. Duration, in Bergson's view, was creativity and memory as an essential component of reality.[80]
According to Martin Heidegger we do not exist inside time, we are time. Hence, the relationship to the past is a present awareness of having been, which allows the past to exist in the present. The relationship to the future is the state of anticipating a potential possibility, task, or engagement. It is related to the human propensity for caring and being concerned, which causes "being ahead of oneself" when thinking of a pending occurrence. Therefore, this concern for a potential occurrence also allows the future to exist in the present. The present becomes an experience, which is qualitative instead of quantitative. Heidegger seems to think this is the way that a linear relationship with time, or temporal existence, is broken or transcended.[81] We are not stuck in sequential time. We are able to remember the past and project into the future; we have a kind of random access to our representation of temporal existence; we can, in our thoughts, step out of (ecstasis) sequential time.[82]
Modern era philosophers asked: is time real or unreal, is time happening all at once or a duration, is time tensed or tenseless, and is there a future to be?
Unreality
In 5th century BC Greece, Antiphon the Sophist, in a fragment preserved from his chief work On Truth, held that: "Time is not a reality (hypostasis), but a concept (noêma) or a measure (metron)." Parmenides went further, maintaining that time, motion, and change were illusions, leading to the paradoxes of his follower Zeno.[84] Time as an illusion is also a common theme in Buddhist thought.[85][86]
These arguments often center on what it means for something to be unreal. Modern physicists generally believe that time is as real as space—though others, such as Julian Barbour, argue quantum equations of the universe take their true form when expressed in the timeless realm containing every possible now or momentary configuration of the universe.[87] J. M. E. McTaggart's 1908 article The Unreality of Time argues that, since every event has the characteristic of being both present and not present (i.e., future or past), that time is a self-contradictory idea.
Another modern philosophical theory called presentism views the past and the future as human-mind interpretations of movement instead of real parts of time (or "dimensions") which coexist with the present. This theory rejects the existence of all direct interaction with the past or the future, holding only the present as tangible. This is one of the philosophical arguments against time travel.[88] This contrasts with eternalism (all time: present, past and future, is real) and the growing block theory (the present and the past are real, but the future is not).
Physical definition
Part of a series on |
Classical mechanics |
---|
Until Einstein's reinterpretation of the physical concepts associated with time and space in 1907, time was considered to be the same everywhere in the universe, with all observers measuring the same time interval for any event.[89] Non-relativistic classical mechanics is based on this Newtonian idea of time. Einstein, in his special theory of relativity,[90] postulated the constancy and finiteness of the speed of light for all observers. He showed that this postulate, together with a reasonable definition for what it means for two events to be simultaneous, requires that distances appear compressed and time intervals appear lengthened for events associated with objects in motion relative to an inertial observer.
The theory of special relativity finds a convenient formulation in
Arrow of time
Unlike space, where an object can travel in the opposite directions (and in 3 dimensions), time appears to have only one dimension and only one direction—the past lies behind, fixed and immutable, while the future lies ahead and is not necessarily fixed. Yet most laws of physics allow any process to proceed both forward and in reverse. There are only a few physical phenomena that violate the reversibility of time. This time directionality is known as the arrow of time. Acknowledged examples of the arrow of time are:[91][92][93]
- Radiative arrow of time, manifested in waves (e.g., light and sound) travelling only expanding (rather than focusing) in time (see light cone);
- Entropic arrow of time: according to the second law of thermodynamicsan isolated system evolves toward a larger disorder rather than orders spontaneously;
- Quantum arrow time, which is related to irreversibility of measurement in quantum mechanics according to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics;
- Weak arrow of time: preference for a certain time direction of weak force in particle physics (see violation of CP symmetry);
- expansion of the Universe after the Big Bang.
The relationships between these different arrows of time is a hotly debated topic in theoretical physics.[94]
The second law of thermodynamics states that entropy must increase over time. Brian Greene theorizes that, according to the equations, the change in entropy occurs symmetrically whether going forward or backward in time. So entropy tends to increase in either direction, and our current low-entropy universe is a statistical aberration, in a similar manner as tossing a coin often enough that eventually heads will result ten times in a row. However, this theory is not supported empirically in local experiment.[95]
Classical mechanics
In non-relativistic classical mechanics, Newton's concept of "relative, apparent, and common time" can be used in the formulation of a prescription for the synchronization of clocks. Events seen by two different observers in motion relative to each other produce a mathematical concept of time that works sufficiently well for describing the everyday phenomena of most people's experience. In the late nineteenth century, physicists encountered problems with the classical understanding of time, in connection with the behavior of electricity and magnetism. The 1860s Maxwell's equations described that light always travels at a constant speed (in a vacuum).[96] However, classical mechanics assumed that motion was measured relative to a fixed reference frame. The Michelson–Morley experiment contradicted the assumption. Einstein later proposed a method of synchronizing clocks using the constant, finite speed of light as the maximum signal velocity. This led directly to the conclusion that observers in motion relative to one another measure different elapsed times for the same event.

Spacetime
Time has historically been closely related with space, the two together merging into spacetime in Einstein's special relativity and general relativity. According to these theories, the concept of time depends on the spatial reference frame of the observer, and the human perception, as well as the measurement by instruments such as clocks, are different for observers in relative motion. For example, if a spaceship carrying a clock flies through space at (very nearly) the speed of light, its crew does not notice a change in the speed of time on board their vessel because everything traveling at the same speed slows down at the same rate (including the clock, the crew's thought processes, and the functions of their bodies). However, to a stationary observer watching the spaceship fly by, the spaceship appears flattened in the direction it is traveling and the clock on board the spaceship appears to move very slowly.
On the other hand, the crew on board the spaceship also perceives the observer as slowed down and flattened along the spaceship's direction of travel, because both are moving at very nearly the speed of light relative to each other. Because the outside universe appears flattened to the spaceship, the crew perceives themselves as quickly traveling between regions of space that (to the stationary observer) are many light years apart. This is reconciled by the fact that the crew's perception of time is different from the stationary observer's; what seems like seconds to the crew might be hundreds of years to the stationary observer. In either case, however, causality remains unchanged: the past is the set of events that can send light signals to an entity and the future is the set of events to which an entity can send light signals.[97][98]
Dilation

Einstein showed in his thought experiments that people travelling at different speeds, while agreeing on cause and effect, measure different time separations between events, and can even observe different chronological orderings between non-causally related events. Though these effects are typically minute in the human experience, the effect becomes much more pronounced for objects moving at speeds approaching the speed of light. Subatomic particles exist for a well-known average fraction of a second in a lab relatively at rest, but when travelling close to the speed of light they are measured to travel farther and exist for much longer than when at rest.
According to the
Einstein (The Meaning of Relativity): "Two events taking place at the points A and B of a system K are simultaneous if they appear at the same instant when observed from the middle point, M, of the interval AB. Time is then defined as the ensemble of the indications of similar clocks, at rest relative to K, which register the same simultaneously." Einstein wrote in his book, Relativity, that simultaneity is also relative, i.e., two events that appear simultaneous to an observer in a particular inertial reference frame need not be judged as simultaneous by a second observer in a different inertial frame of reference.
According to general relativity, time also runs slower in stronger gravitational fields; this is gravitational time dilation.[99] The effect of the dilation becomes more noticeable in a mass-dense object. A famous example of time dilation is a thought experiment of a subject approaching the event horizon of a black hole. As a consequence of how gravitational fields warp spacetime, the subject will experience gravitational time dilation. From the perspective of the subject itself, they will experience time normally. Meanwhile, an observer from the outside will see the subject move closer to the black hole until the extreme, in which the subject appears 'frozen' in time and eventually fade to nothingness due to the diminishing amount of light returning.[100][101]
Relativistic versus Newtonian

The animations visualise the different treatments of time in the Newtonian and the relativistic descriptions. At the heart of these differences are the Galilean and Lorentz transformations applicable in the Newtonian and relativistic theories, respectively. In the figures, the vertical direction indicates time. The horizontal direction indicates distance (only one spatial dimension is taken into account), and the thick dashed curve is the spacetime trajectory ("world line") of the observer. The small dots indicate specific (past and future) events in spacetime. The slope of the world line (deviation from being vertical) gives the relative velocity to the observer.
In the Newtonian description these changes are such that time is absolute:[102] the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event occurs in the 'now' (i.e., whether an event passes the horizontal line through the observer). However, in the relativistic description the observability of events is absolute: the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event passes the "light cone" of the observer. Notice that with the change from a Newtonian to a relativistic description, the concept of absolute time is no longer applicable: events move up and down in the figure depending on the acceleration of the observer.
Quantization
Time quantization refers to the theory that time has the smallest possible unit. Time quantization is a hypothetical concept. In the modern established physical theories like the
Travel
Time travel is the concept of moving backwards or forwards to different points in time, in a manner analogous to moving through space, and different from the normal "flow" of time to an earthbound observer. In this view, all points in time (including future times) "persist" in some way. Time travel has been a plot device in fiction since the 19th century. Travelling backwards or forwards in time has never been verified as a process, and doing so presents many theoretical problems and contradictory logic which to date have not been overcome. Any technological device, whether fictional or hypothetical, that is used to achieve time travel is known as a time machine.
A central problem with time travel to the past is the violation of causality; should an effect precede its cause, it would give rise to the possibility of a temporal paradox. Some interpretations of time travel resolve this by accepting the possibility of travel between branch points, parallel realities, or universes. The many-worlds interpretation has been used as a way to solve causality paradoxes arising from time travel. Any quantum event creates another branching timeline, and all possible outcomes coexist without any wave function collapse.[104] This interpretation was an alternative but is opposite from the Copenhagen interpretation, which suggests that wave functions do collapse.[105] In science, hypothetical faster-than-light particles are known as tachyons; the mathematics of Einstein's relativity suggests that they would have an imaginary rest mass. Some interpretations suggest that it might move backward in time. General relativity permits the existence of closed timelike curves, which could allow an observer to travel back in time to the same space.[106] Though for the Gödel metric, such an occurrence requires a globally rotating universe, which has been contradicted by observations of the redshifts of distant galaxies and the cosmic background radiation.[107]
Another solution to the problem of causality-based temporal paradoxes is that such paradoxes cannot arise simply because they have not arisen. As illustrated in numerous works of fiction,
Perception

The specious present refers to the time duration wherein one's perceptions are considered to be in the present. The experienced present is said to be 'specious' in that, unlike the objective present, it is an interval and not a durationless instant. The term specious present was first introduced by the psychologist E. R. Clay, and later developed by William James.[108]
Biopsychology
The brain's judgment of time is known to be a highly distributed system, including at least the
Psychoactive drugs can impair the judgment of time. Stimulants can lead both humans and rats to overestimate time intervals,[112][113] while depressants can have the opposite effect.[114] The level of activity in the brain of neurotransmitters such as dopamine and norepinephrine may be the reason for this.[115] Such chemicals will either excite or inhibit the firing of neurons in the brain, with a greater firing rate allowing the brain to register the occurrence of more events within a given interval (speed up time) and a decreased firing rate reducing the brain's capacity to distinguish events occurring within a given interval (slow down time).[116]
Psychologists assert that time seems to go faster with age, but the literature on this age-related perception of time remains controversial.[117] Those who support this notion argue that young people, having more excitatory neurotransmitters, are able to cope with faster external events.[116] Some also argued that the perception of time is also influenced by memory and how much one have experienced; for example, as one get older, they will have spend less part of their total life waiting a month.[118] Meanwhile children's expanding cognitive abilities allow them to understand time in a different way. Two- and three-year-olds' understanding of time is mainly limited to "now and not now". Five- and six-year-olds can grasp the ideas of past, present, and future. Seven- to ten-year-olds can use clocks and calendars.[119] Socioemotional selectivity theory proposed that when people perceive their time as open-ended and nebulous, they focus more on future-oriented goals.[120]
Spatial conceptualization
Although time is regarded as an abstract concept, there is increasing evidence that time is conceptualized in the mind in terms of space.[121] That is, instead of thinking about time in a general, abstract way, humans think about time in a spatial way and mentally organize it as such. Using space to think about time allows humans to mentally organize temporal events in a specific way. This spatial representation of time is often represented in the mind as a mental timeline (MTL).[122] These origins are shaped by many environmental factors.[121] Literacy appears to play a large role in the different types of MTLs, as reading/writing direction provides an everyday temporal orientation that differs from culture to culture.[122] In Western cultures, the MTL may unfold rightward (with the past on the left and the future on the right) since people mostly read and write from left to right.[122] Western calendars also continue this trend by placing the past on the left with the future progressing toward the right. Conversely, speakers of Arabic, Farsi, Urdu, and Hebrew read from right to left, and their MTLs unfold leftward (past on the right with future on the left); evidence suggests these speakers organize time events in their minds like this as well.[122]
There is also evidence that some cultures use an allocentric spatialization, often based on environmental features.
Use
In sociology and anthropology, time discipline is the general name given to social and economic rules, conventions, customs, and expectations governing the measurement of time, the social currency and awareness of time measurements, and people's expectations concerning the observance of these customs by others. Arlie Russell Hochschild[124][125] and Norbert Elias[126] have written on the use of time from a sociological perspective.
The use of time is an important issue in understanding human behavior, education, and travel behavior. Time-use research is a developing field of study. The question concerns how time is allocated across a number of activities (such as time spent at home, at work, shopping, etc.). Time use changes with technology, as the television or the Internet created new opportunities to use time in different ways. However, some aspects of time use are relatively stable over long periods of time, such as the amount of time spent traveling to work, which despite major changes in transport, has been observed to be about 20–30 minutes one-way for a large number of cities over a long period.
Time management is the organization of tasks or events by first estimating how much time a task requires and when it must be completed, and adjusting events that would interfere with its completion so it is done in the appropriate amount of time. Calendars and day planners are common examples of time management tools.
Sequence of events
A sequence of events, or series of events, is a sequence of items, facts, events, actions, changes, or procedural steps, arranged in time order (chronological order), often with causality relationships among the items.[127][128][129] Because of causality, cause precedes effect, or cause and effect may appear together in a single item, but effect never precedes cause. A sequence of events can be presented in text, tables, charts, or timelines. The description of the items or events may include a timestamp. A sequence of events that includes the time along with place or location information to describe a sequential path may be referred to as a world line.
Uses of a sequence of events include stories,
See also
- List of UTC timing centers
- Loschmidt's paradox
- Time metrology
Organizations
- Antiquarian Horological Society – AHS (United Kingdom)
- Chronometrophilia (Switzerland)
- Deutsche Gesellschaft für Chronometrie – DGC (Germany)
- National Association of Watch and Clock Collectors – NAWCC (United States)
Miscellaneous arts and sciences
|
Miscellaneous units
|
References
- ^
"Time". Oxford Dictionaries. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 4 July 2012. Retrieved 18 May 2017.
The indefinite continued progress of existence and events in the past, present, and future regarded as a whole
- ^ a b *"Webster's New World College Dictionary". 2010. Archived from the original on 5 August 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
1.indefinite, unlimited duration in which things are considered as happening in the past, present, or future; every moment there has ever been or ever will be… a system of measuring duration 2.the period between two events or during which something exists, happens, or acts; measured or measurable interval
- "The American Heritage Stedman's Medical Dictionary". 2002. Archived from the original on 5 March 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
A duration or relation of events expressed in terms of past, present, and future, and measured in units such as minutes, hours, days, months, or years.
- "Collins Language.com". HarperCollins. 2011. Archived from the original on 2 October 2011. Retrieved 18 December 2011.
1. The continuous passage of existence in which events pass from a state of potentiality in the future, through the present, to a state of finality in the past. 2. physics a quantity measuring duration, usually with reference to a periodic process such as the rotation of the earth or the frequency of electromagnetic radiation emitted from certain atoms. In classical mechanics, time is absolute in the sense that the time of an event is independent of the observer. According to the theory of relativity it depends on the observer's frame of reference. Time is considered as a fourth coordinate required, along with three spatial coordinates, to specify an event.
- "The American Heritage Science Dictionary @dictionary.com". 2002. Archived from the original on 5 March 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
1. A continuous, measurable quantity in which events occur in a sequence proceeding from the past through the present to the future. 2a. An interval separating two points of this quantity; a duration. 2b. A system or reference frame in which such intervals are measured or such quantities are calculated.
- "Eric Weisstein's World of Science". 2007. Archived from the original on 29 November 2017. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
A quantity used to specify the order in which events occurred and measure the amount by which one event preceded or followed another. In special relativity, ct (where c is the speed of light and t is time), plays the role of a fourth dimension.
- "The American Heritage Stedman's Medical Dictionary". 2002. Archived from the original on 5 March 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- ^ "Time". The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language (Fourth ed.). 2011. Archived from the original on 19 July 2012.
A nonspatial continuum in which events occur in apparently irreversible succession from the past through the present to the future.
- ^ Merriam-Webster Dictionary Archived 8 May 2012 at the Wayback Machine the measured or measurable period during which an action, process, or condition exists or continues: duration; a nonspatial continuum which is measured in terms of events that succeed one another from past through present to future
- ^ Compact Oxford English Dictionary A limited stretch or space of continued existence, as the interval between two successive events or acts, or the period through which an action, condition, or state continues. (1971).
- ^ a b c *"Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". 2010. Archived from the original on 11 April 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
Time is what clocks measure. We use time to place events in sequence one after the other, and we use time to compare how long events last... Among philosophers of physics, the most popular short answer to the question "What is physical time?" is that it is not a substance or object but rather a special system of relations among instantaneous events. This working definition is offered by Adolf Grünbaum who applies the contemporary mathematical theory of continuity to physical processes, and he says time is a linear continuum of instants and is a distinguished one-dimensional sub-space of four-dimensional spacetime.
- "Dictionary.com Unabridged, based on Random House Dictionary". 2010. Archived from the original on 5 March 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
1. the system of those sequential relations that any event has to any other, as past, present, or future; indefinite and continuous duration regarded as that in which events succeed one another.... 3. (sometimes initial capital letter) a system or method of measuring or reckoning the passage of time: mean time; apparent time; Greenwich Time. 4. a limited period or interval, as between two successive events: a long time.... 14. a particular or definite point in time, as indicated by a clock: What time is it? ... 18. an indefinite, frequently prolonged period or duration in the future: Time will tell if what we have done here today was right.
- Ivey, Donald G.; Hume, J.N.P. (1974). Physics. Vol. 1. Ronald Press. p. 65. Archived from the original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved 7 May 2020.
Our operational definition of time is that time is what clocks measure.
- "Dictionary.com Unabridged, based on Random House Dictionary". 2010. Archived from the original on 5 March 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- ^ a b c Le Poidevin, Robin (Winter 2004). "The Experience and Perception of Time". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 22 October 2013. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- ISBN 978-0-684-81822-1
- ISBN 978-0-19-921540-9.
- ISBN 978-0-525-95133-9.
- ^ "The Feynman Lectures on Physics Vol. I Ch. 5: Time and Distance". www.feynmanlectures.caltech.edu. Retrieved 15 December 2023.
- ^ "Official Baseball Rules – 8.03 and 8.04" (Free PDF download). Major League Baseball. 2011. Archived (PDF) from the original on 1 July 2017. Retrieved 18 May 2017.
Rule 8.03 Such preparatory pitches shall not consume more than one minute of time...Rule 8.04 When the bases are unoccupied, the pitcher shall deliver the ball to the batter within 12 seconds...The 12-second timing starts when the pitcher is in possession of the ball and the batter is in the box, alert to the pitcher. The timing stops when the pitcher releases the ball.
- ^ "Guinness Book of Baseball World Records". Guinness World Records, Ltd. Archived from the original on 6 June 2012. Retrieved 7 July 2012.
The record for the fastest time for circling the bases is 13.3 seconds, set by Evar Swanson at Columbus, Ohio in 1932...The greatest reliably recorded speed at which a baseball has been pitched is 100.9 mph by Lynn Nolan Ryan (California Angels) at Anaheim Stadium in California on 20 August 1974.
- ISBN 978-0-07-159138-6. Archivedfrom the original on 18 August 2020. Retrieved 30 July 2019. 108 pages.
- ^ Duff, Okun, Veneziano, ibid. p. 3. "There is no well established terminology for the fundamental constants of Nature. ... The absence of accurately defined terms or the uses (i.e., actually misuses) of ill-defined terms lead to confusion and proliferation of wrong statements."
- ^ a b
Burnham, Douglas: Staffordshire University (2006). "Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) Metaphysics – 7. Space, Time, and Indiscernibles". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 14 May 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
First of all, Leibniz finds the idea that space and time might be substances or substance-like absurd (see, for example, "Correspondence with Clarke," Leibniz's Fourth Paper, §8ff). In short, an empty space would be a substance with no properties; it will be a substance that even God cannot modify or destroy.... That is, space and time are internal or intrinsic features of the complete concepts of things, not extrinsic.... Leibniz's view has two major implications. First, there is no absolute location in either space or time; location is always the situation of an object or event relative to other objects and events. Second, space and time are not in themselves real (that is, not substances). Space and time are, rather, ideal. Space and time are just metaphysically illegitimate ways of perceiving certain virtual relations between substances. They are phenomena or, strictly speaking, illusions (although they are illusions that are well-founded upon the internal properties of substances).... It is sometimes convenient to think of space and time as something "out there," over and above the entities and their relations to each other, but this convenience must not be confused with reality. Space is nothing but the order of co-existent objects; time nothing but the order of successive events. This is usually called a relational theory of space and time.
- ISBN 978-0-07-012436-3. Archivedfrom the original on 31 December 2013. Retrieved 1 November 2016.
- .
- .
Thus, the causal structure poset (M, ≺) of a future and past distinguishing spacetime is equivalent to its conformal geometry.
- .
In our opinion, it is not possible to reconciliate and integrate into a common scheme the absolute and non-dynamical character of Newtonian time of canonical quantization and path integral approaches with the relativistic and dynamical character of time in general relativity.
- ^ Shavit, Joseph (18 July 2024). "Revolutionary theory finally unites quantum mechanics and Einstein's theory of general relativity". The Brighter Side of News. Archived from the original on 4 August 2024. Retrieved 4 August 2024.
The prevailing consensus has been that Einstein's theory of gravity must be modified to fit within the framework of quantum theory [...] when it comes to merging these two theories into a single, comprehensive framework, the scientific community has hit a roadblock.
- ISBN 978-0-19-850413-9.
- ^ Rudgley, Richard (1999). The Lost Civilizations of the Stone Age. New York: Simon & Schuster. pp. 86–105.
- ^ Van Stone, Mark (2011). "The Maya Long Count Calendar: An Introduction". Archaeoastronomy. 24: 8–11.
- ^ Davies, Diane. "The Maya Calendar Explained". Maya Archaeologist. Archived from the original on 26 February 2025. Retrieved 26 February 2025.
- ^ "French republican calendar | Revolutionary period, decimal system, reform". Britannica. Archived from the original on 8 March 2025. Retrieved 26 February 2025.
- ^ "Education". Archived from the original on 1 May 2019. Retrieved 1 July 2018.
- ^ Lombardi, Michael A. (5 March 2007). "Why is a minute divided into 60 seconds, an hour into 60 minutes, yet there are only 24 hours in a day?". Scientific American. Archived from the original on 20 September 2023. Retrieved 26 February 2025.
- ^ "A Walk Through Time - Early Clocks". National Institute of Standards and Technology. 12 August 2009. Archived from the original on 2 August 2016. Retrieved 26 February 2025.
- ISBN 978-0-15-600649-1.
- ISBN 978-90-474-4360-5.
- ^ "The alarm clock of Plato (5th c. B.C.) - The first awakening device in human history". Museum of the Ancient Greek Technology. 28 November 2023. Retrieved 25 February 2025.
- ISSN 2191-9151.
- ^ "Byrhtferth of Ramsey". Encyclopædia Britannica. 2008. Archived from the original on 14 June 2020. Retrieved 15 September 2008.
- ^ "atom", Oxford English Dictionary, Draft Revision September 2008 (contains relevant citations from Byrhtferth's Enchiridion)
- ^ Barnett, ibid, p. 37.
- ISBN 1-85285-451-0
- ^ Watson, E., (1979) "The St Albans Clock of Richard of Wallingford". Antiquarian Horology, pp. 372–384.
- ISBN 0-06-621173-5[page needed]
- ^ "History of Clocks." About.com Inventors. About.com, n.d. Web. 21 February 2016.
- ^ Tikkanen, Amy (15 January 2009). "22 Questions About Time and Timekeeping Answered". Britannica. Archived from the original on 12 March 2025. Retrieved 25 February 2025.
- ^ "NIST Unveils Chip-Scale Atomic Clock". NIST. 27 August 2004. Archived from the original on 22 May 2011. Retrieved 9 June 2011.
- ^ "New atomic clock can keep time for 200 million years: Super-precise instruments vital to deep space navigation". Vancouver Sun. 16 February 2008. Archived from the original on 11 February 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- ^ "NIST-F1 Cesium Fountain Clock". Archived from the original on 25 March 2020. Retrieved 24 July 2015.
- ^ "12 attoseconds is the world record for shortest controllable time". 12 May 2010. Archived from the original on 5 August 2011. Retrieved 19 April 2012.
- ^ Andrewes, William J. H. (1 February 2006). "A Chronicle Of Timekeeping". Scientific American. Retrieved 26 February 2025.
- ISBN 978-1-55939-779-7.
- ^ "Chichén Itzá: Venus Cycle". Travel. 27 February 2012. Archived from the original on 8 May 2024. Retrieved 8 May 2024.
- ISBN 978-0-86554-058-3. Archived from the original on 3 April 2017. Retrieved 20 August 2015.points out, is linear. [...] In the Judaeo-Christian religions – Judaism, Christianity, Islam – history is taken seriously, and linear time is accepted.
Profane time, as Eliade
- ISBN 978-90-04-14688-4. Archivedfrom the original on 24 September 2015. Retrieved 20 August 2015.
[...] God produces a creation with a directional time structure [...].
- ISBN 978-0-8028-4635-8. Archivedfrom the original on 19 September 2015. Retrieved 20 August 2015.
We need to note the close ties between teleology, eschatology, and utopia. In Christian theology, the understanding of the teleology of particular actions is ultimately related to the teleology of history in general, which is the concern of eschatology.
- ^ Staley, Kevin M. (2006). "Omniscience, Time, and Eternity: Is Aquinas Inconsistent?" (PDF). The Saint Anselm Journal.
- ^ Barr, Stephen M. (7 February 2020). "St. Augustine's Relativistic Theory of Time". Church Life Journal. Archived from the original on 15 April 2024. Retrieved 28 February 2025.
- ^ Selzer, Mark Albert. "Augustine on Time: Human Time, Divine Eternity, and Why the Former is Really the Latter". California State University, East Bay. Archived from the original on 15 January 2025. Retrieved 28 February 2025.
- ^ Ecclesiastes 1:4–11
- ^ Ecclesiastes 3:1–8
- ^ "(Dictionary Entry)". Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon. Archived from the original on 7 May 2022. Retrieved 13 July 2015.
- ^ New Myths and Meanings in Jewish New Moon Rituals David M. Rosen, Victoria P. Rosen Ethnology, Vol. 39, No. 3 (Summer, 2000), pp. 263–277 (referencing Yerushalmi 1989)
- ISBN 978-90-04-18284-4. Archivedfrom the original on 13 May 2016. Retrieved 27 February 2016.
- ISBN 978-0-520-93231-9. Archived from the original on 19 August 2020. Retrieved 7 May 2020. Extract of page 111 Archived 11 May 2022 at the Wayback Machine
- from the original on 13 June 2024. Retrieved 13 June 2024.
- ^
Rynasiewicz, Robert: Johns Hopkins University (12 August 2004). "Newton's Views on Space, Time, and Motion". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Archived from the original on 16 July 2012. Retrieved 5 February 2012.
Newton did not regard space and time as genuine substances (as are, paradigmatically, bodies and minds), but rather as real entities with their own manner of existence as necessitated by God's existence ... To paraphrase: Absolute, true, and mathematical time, from its own nature, passes equably without relation to anything external, and thus without reference to any change or way of measuring of time (e.g., the hour, day, month, or year).
- ^ Markosian, Ned. "Time". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition). Archived from the original on 14 September 2006. Retrieved 23 September 2011.
The opposing view, normally referred to either as "Platonism with Respect to Time" or as "Absolutism with Respect to Time", has been defended by Plato, Newton, and others. On this view, time is like an empty container into which events may be placed; but it is a container that exists independently of whether or not anything is placed in it.
- ^
Mattey, G. J. (22 January 1997). "Critique of Pure Reason, Lecture notes: Philosophy 175 UC Davis". Archived from the original on 14 March 2005. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
What is correct in the Leibnizian view was its anti-metaphysical stance. Space and time do not exist in and of themselves, but in some sense are the product of the way we represent things. The[y] are ideal, though not in the sense in which Leibniz thought they are ideal (figments of the imagination). The ideality of space is its mind-dependence: it is only a condition of sensibility.... Kant concluded ... "absolute space is not an object of outer sensation; it is rather a fundamental concept which first of all makes possible all such outer sensation."...Much of the argumentation pertaining to space is applicable, mutatis mutandis, to time, so I will not rehearse the arguments. As space is the form of outer intuition, so time is the form of inner intuition.... Kant claimed that time is real, it is "the real form of inner intuition."
- ^
McCormick, Matt (2006). "Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) Metaphysics: 4. Kant's Transcendental Idealism". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 26 April 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
Time, Kant argues, is also necessary as a form or condition of our intuitions of objects. The idea of time itself cannot be gathered from experience because succession and simultaneity of objects, the phenomena that would indicate the passage of time, would be impossible to represent if we did not already possess the capacity to represent objects in time.... Another way to put the point is to say that the fact that the mind of the knower makes the a priori contribution does not mean that space and time or the categories are mere figments of the imagination. Kant is an empirical realist about the world we experience; we can know objects as they appear to us. He gives a robust defense of science and the study of the natural world from his argument about the mind's role in making nature. All discursive, rational beings must conceive of the physical world as spatially and temporally unified, he argues.
- ^
Carrol, Sean (2010). "Chapter One, Section Two, Plume". ISBN 978-0-452-29654-1.
As human beings we 'feel' the passage of time.
- ^ Lehar, Steve. (2000). The Function of Conscious Experience: An Analogical Paradigm of Perception and Behavior Archived 21 October 2015 at the Wayback Machine, Consciousness and Cognition.
- ^ a b c "Philosophy of Time – Exactly What Is Time?". Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
- ^ a b c d e f "Ancient Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?". Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
- ^ from the original on 2 April 2019. Retrieved 11 April 2019.
- ISBN 978-0-415-09558-7.
- ^ Dagobert Runes, Dictionary of Philosophy, p. 318.
- ^ Hardie, R. P.; Gaye, R. K. "Physics by Aristotle". Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Archived from the original on 26 June 2014. Retrieved 4 May 2014. "Time then is a kind of number. (Number, we must note, is used in two senses – both of what is counted or the countable and also of that with which we count. Time obviously is what is counted, not that with which we count: there are different kinds of thing.) [...] It is clear, then, that time is 'number of movement in respect of the before and after', and is continuous since it is an attribute of what is continuous."
- ^ Augustine of Hippo. Confessions. Archived from the original on 19 January 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011. Book 11, Chapter 14.
- ^ a b c d e "Early Modern Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?". Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
- ^ Gottfried Martin, Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science.
- ^ Jankowiak, Tim. "Immanuel Kant". Archived from the original on 23 May 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2019.
- ^ Kant, Immanuel (1787). The Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edition. Archived from the original on 13 April 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011. translated by J.M.D. Meiklejohn, eBooks@Adelaide, 2004
- ^ Bergson, Henri (1907) Creative Evolution. trans. by Arthur Mitchell. Mineola: Dover, 1998.
- ISBN 978-90-04-09583-0. Archivedfrom the original on 20 August 2020. Retrieved 30 July 2019.
- ISBN 978-0-631-19770-6. Archived from the original on 19 August 2020. Retrieved 30 July 2019.)
{{cite book}}
: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help - ^ a b c d "Modern Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?". Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
- ^ Foundalis, Harry. "You are about to disappear". Archived from the original on 12 May 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- ^ Huston, Tom. "Buddhism and the illusion of time". Archived from the original on 8 July 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- ISBN 978-0-19-509336-0. Archivedfrom the original on 19 August 2020. Retrieved 19 May 2018.
- ^ Folger, Tim (30 November 2000). "From Here to Eternity". Discover Magazine. Retrieved 26 February 2025.
- ^ Sakon, Takeshi (2020). "Presentists Should Not Believe in Time Travel". Philosophy of Science. 53 (2) – via Osaka City University.
- ISBN 0-88275-478-5(1977 edition), pp. 10–13
- ISBN 0-486-60081-5, See pp. 37–65 for an English translation of Einstein's original 1905 paper.
- ISSN 2522-5820.
- ISBN 978-3-319-44417-8, retrieved 1 March 2025
- ISBN 978-1-139-22570-0.
- ISBN 978-0-449-90630-9.
- ISBN 978-0-14-195995-5. Archivedfrom the original on 20 August 2020. Retrieved 16 September 2017.
- ISSN 2278-067X.
- ^ "Albert Einstein's Theory of Relativity". YouTube. 30 November 2011. Archived from the original on 17 October 2013. Retrieved 24 September 2013.
- ^ "Time Travel: Einstein's big idea (Theory of Relativity)". YouTube. 9 January 2007. Archived from the original on 17 October 2013. Retrieved 24 September 2013.
- .
- ^ Gohd, Chelsea (3 May 2023). "What Happens When Something Gets 'Too Close' to a Black Hole?". NASA Science. Retrieved 1 March 2025.
- ^ Gunn, Alastair (12 January 2025). "The (very strange) reason black holes are secret time machines". BBC Science Focus Magazine. Retrieved 1 March 2025.
- ISBN 978-3-642-97599-8.
- ^ Lewton, Thomas (10 July 2023). "The Physicist Who Bets That Gravity Can't Be Quantized". Quanta Magazine. Archived from the original on 13 February 2025. Retrieved 2 March 2025.
- arXiv:2405.06924v1. Archivedfrom the original on 31 December 2024. Retrieved 28 February 2025 – via arXiv.
- from the original on 3 February 2025. Retrieved 28 February 2025.
- ISSN 0264-9381.
- ISSN 2576-4403.
- S2CID 16379171. Archived from the original(PDF) on 16 February 2008. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- ^ Wada Y, Masuda T, Noguchi K, 2005, "Temporal illusion called 'kappa effect' in event perception" Perception 34 ECVP Abstract Supplement.
- ^ Adler, Robert. "Look how time flies". Archived from the original on 14 June 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- PMID 541126.
- PMID 17434690.
- ^ Cheng, Ruey-Kuang; Macdonald, Christopher J.; Meck, Warren H. (2006). "Differential effects of cocaine and ketamine on time estimation: Implications for neurobiological models of interval timing" (online abstract). from the original on 10 August 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- S2CID 25928542.
- PMID 18562621.
- ^ ISBN 978-0-7566-5441-2. Archivedfrom the original on 13 May 2016. Retrieved 27 February 2016.
- ISBN 978-0-306-46439-3. Archived from the original on 21 July 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011. Extract of page 54 Archived 13 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine
- ^ Wilson, Jillian (16 December 2022). "Time Flies By Faster As We Get Older. Here's Why". HuffPost. Retrieved 26 February 2025.
- ^ Kennedy-Moore, Eileen (28 March 2014). "Time Management for Kids". Psychology Today. Archived from the original on 30 July 2022. Retrieved 26 April 2014.
- PMID 30048830.
- ^ S2CID 17215084.
- ^ S2CID 14646964.
- ^ S2CID 22097776.
- ISBN 978-0-8050-4471-3.
- ^ Russell Hochschild, Arlie (20 April 1997). "There's no place like work". The New York Times Magazine. Archived from the original on 23 March 2017. Retrieved 20 February 2017.
- ISBN 978-0-631-15798-4.
- ^ "Sequence – Order of Important Events" (PDF). Austin Independent School District. 2009. Archived from the original (PDF) on 27 September 2011.
- ^ "Sequence of Events Worksheets". Reference.com. Archived from the original on 13 October 2010.
- ^ Compiled by David Luckham & Roy Schulte (23 August 2011). "Event Processing Glossary – Version 2.0". Complex Event Processing. Archived from the original on 15 October 2011.
- About.com. Archivedfrom the original on 4 September 2011.
- ^ Piasecki, David J. "Inventory Accuracy Glossary". AccuracyBook.com (OPS Publishing). Archived from the original on 3 September 2011.
- ^ "Utility Communications Architecture (UCA) glossary". NettedAutomation. Archived from the original on 10 December 2011.
Further reading
- ISBN 978-0-19-514592-2.
- Craig Callendar, Introducing Time, Icon Books, 2010, ISBN 978-1-84831-120-6
- Das, Tushar Kanti (1990). The Time Dimension: An Interdisciplinary Guide. New York: Praeger. ISBN 978-0-275-92681-6. – Research bibliography
- ISBN 978-0-684-81822-1.
- ISBN 978-0-262-56003-0.
- ISBN 978-0-393-02001-4.
- Benjamin Gal-Or, Cosmology, Physics and Philosophy, Springer Verlag, 1981, 1983, 1987, ISBN 0-387-90581-2, 0-387-96526-2.
- Charlie Gere, (2005) Art, Time and Technology: Histories of the Disappearing Body, Berg
- Highfield, Roger (1992). Arrow of Time: A Voyage through Science to Solve Time's Greatest Mystery. Random House. ISBN 978-0-449-90723-8.
- ISBN 978-0-674-00282-1.
- Lebowitz, Joel L. (2008). "Time's arrow and Boltzmann's entropy". Scholarpedia. 3 (4): 3448. .
- ISBN 978-0-691-12201-4.
- Morris, Richard (1985). Time's Arrows: Scientific Attitudes Toward Time. New York: Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-671-61766-0.
- ISBN 978-0-19-286198-6. Archived from the originalon 26 December 2010. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- Price, Huw (1996). Time's Arrow and Archimedes' Point. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-511798-1. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- ISBN 978-0-486-40926-9.
- Rovelli, Carlo (2006). What is time? What is space?. Rome: Di Renzo Editore. ISBN 978-88-8323-146-9. Archived from the originalon 27 January 2007.
- Rovelli, Carlo (2018). The Order of Time. New York: Riverhead. ISBN 978-0735216105.
- Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of Epimetheus
- Roberto Mangabeira Unger and Lee Smolin, ISBN 978-1-107-07406-4.
- Whitrow, Gerald J. (1973). The Nature of Time. Holt, Rinehart and Wilson (New York).
- Whitrow, Gerald J. (1980). The Natural Philosophy of Time. Clarendon Press (Oxford).
- Whitrow, Gerald J. (1988). Time in History. The evolution of our general awareness of time and temporal perspective. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-285211-3.
External links
- Different systems of measuring time (archived 16 October 2015).
- Time on In Our Time at the BBC.
- "Time". Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary. Merriam-Webster.
- Time in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, by Bradley Dowden.
- Le Poidevin, Robin (Winter 2004). "The Experience and Perception of Time". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
- Time Expansion Experiences: Time may just be a creation of our minds by Steve Taylor Ph.D. January 31, 2025, Psychology Today.