Cantor's theorem
In mathematical set theory, Cantor's theorem is a fundamental result which states that, for any set , the set of all subsets of known as the power set of has a strictly greater cardinality than itself.
For finite sets, Cantor's theorem can be seen to be true by simple enumeration of the number of subsets. Counting the empty set as a subset, a set with elements has a total of subsets, and the theorem holds because for all
Much more significant is Cantor's discovery of an argument that is applicable to any set, and shows that the theorem holds for infinite sets also. As a consequence, the cardinality of the real numbers, which is the same as that of the power set of the integers, is strictly larger than the cardinality of the integers; see Cardinality of the continuum for details.
The theorem is named for Georg Cantor, who first stated and proved it at the end of the 19th century. Cantor's theorem had immediate and important consequences for the philosophy of mathematics. For instance, by iteratively taking the power set of an infinite set and applying Cantor's theorem, we obtain an endless hierarchy of infinite cardinals, each strictly larger than the one before it. Consequently, the theorem implies that there is no largest cardinal number (colloquially, "there's no largest infinity").
Proof
Cantor's argument is elegant and remarkably simple. The complete proof is presented below, with detailed explanations to follow.
Theorem (Cantor) — Let be a map from set to its power set . Then is not
exists via the axiom schema of specification, and because .
Assume is surjective.
Then there exists a such that .
From for all in , we deduce via universal instantiation.
The previous deduction yields a contradiction of the form , since .
Therefore, is not surjective, via reductio ad absurdum.
We know injective maps from to exist. For example, a function such that .
Consequently, . ∎
By definition of cardinality, we have for any two sets and if and only if there is an
This means, by definition, that for all , if and only if . For all the sets and cannot be equal because was constructed from elements of whose images under did not include themselves. For all either or . If then cannot equal because by assumption and by definition. If then cannot equal because by assumption and by the definition of .
Equivalently, and slightly more formally, we have just proved that the existence of such that implies the following contradiction:
Therefore, by reductio ad absurdum, the assumption must be false.[3] Thus there is no such that ; in other words, is not in the image of and does not map onto every element of the power set of , i.e., is not surjective.
Finally, to complete the proof, we need to exhibit an injective function from to its power set. Finding such a function is trivial: just map to the singleton set . The argument is now complete, and we have established the strict inequality for any set that .
Another way to think of the proof is that , empty or non-empty, is always in the power set of . For to be onto, some element of must map to . But that leads to a contradiction: no element of can map to because that would contradict the criterion of membership in , thus the element mapping to must not be an element of meaning that it satisfies the criterion for membership in , another contradiction. So the assumption that an element of maps to must be false; and cannot be onto.
Because of the double occurrence of in the expression "", this is a diagonal argument. For a countable (or finite) set, the argument of the proof given above can be illustrated by constructing a table in which
- each row is labelled by a unique from , in this order. is assumed to admit a linear order so that such table can be constructed.
- each column of the table is labelled by a unique from the power set of ; the columns are ordered by the argument to , i.e. the column labels are , ..., in this order.
- the intersection of each row and column records a true/false bit whether .
Given the order chosen for the row and column labels, the main diagonal of this table thus records whether for each . One such table will be the following: The set constructed in the previous paragraphs coincides with the row labels for the subset of entries on this main diagonal (which in above example, coloured red) where the table records that is false.[3] Each row records the values of the indicator function of the set corresponding to the column. The indicator function of coincides with the
Despite the simplicity of the above proof, it is rather difficult for an
When A is countably infinite
Let us examine the proof for the specific case when is
Suppose that is
contains infinite subsets of , e.g. the set of all positive even numbers , along with the empty set .
Now that we have an idea of what the elements of are, let us attempt to pair off each
Given such a pairing, some natural numbers are paired with subsets that contain the very same number. For instance, in our example the number 2 is paired with the subset {1, 2, 3}, which contains 2 as a member. Let us call such numbers selfish. Other natural numbers are paired with subsets that do not contain them. For instance, in our example the number 1 is paired with the subset {4, 5}, which does not contain the number 1. Call these numbers non-selfish. Likewise, 3 and 4 are non-selfish.
Using this idea, let us build a special set of natural numbers. This set will provide the contradiction we seek. Let be the set of all non-selfish natural numbers. By definition, the power set contains all sets of natural numbers, and so it contains this set as an element. If the mapping is bijective, must be paired off with some natural number, say . However, this causes a problem. If is in , then is selfish because it is in the corresponding set, which contradicts the definition of . If is not in , then it is non-selfish and it should instead be a member of . Therefore, no such element which maps to can exist.
Since there is no natural number which can be paired with , we have contradicted our original supposition, that there is a bijection between and .
Note that the set may be empty. This would mean that every natural number maps to a subset of natural numbers that contains . Then, every number maps to a nonempty set and no number maps to the empty set. But the empty set is a member of , so the mapping still does not cover .
Through this proof by contradiction we have proven that the cardinality of and cannot be equal. We also know that the cardinality of cannot be less than the cardinality of because contains all singletons, by definition, and these singletons form a "copy" of inside of . Therefore, only one possibility remains, and that is that the cardinality of is strictly greater than the cardinality of , proving Cantor's theorem.
Related paradoxes
Cantor's theorem and its proof are closely related to two paradoxes of set theory.
Cantor's paradox is the name given to a contradiction following from Cantor's theorem together with the assumption that there is a set containing all sets, the universal set . In order to distinguish this paradox from the next one discussed below, it is important to note what this contradiction is. By Cantor's theorem for any set . On the other hand, all elements of are sets, and thus contained in , therefore .[1]
Another paradox can be derived from the proof of Cantor's theorem by instantiating the function f with the identity function; this turns Cantor's diagonal set into what is sometimes called the Russell set of a given set A:[1]
The proof of Cantor's theorem is straightforwardly adapted to show that assuming a set of all sets U exists, then considering its Russell set RU leads to the contradiction:
This argument is known as
Had we used
Despite the syntactical similarities between the Russell set (in either variant) and the Cantor diagonal set, Alonzo Church emphasized that Russell's paradox is independent of considerations of cardinality and its underlying notions like one-to-one correspondence.[5]
History
Cantor gave essentially this proof in a paper published in 1891 "Über eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre",
Ernst Zermelo has a theorem (which he calls "Cantor's Theorem") that is identical to the form above in the paper that became the foundation of modern set theory ("Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I"), published in 1908. See Zermelo set theory.
Generalizations
Lawvere's fixed-point theorem provides for a broad generalization of Cantor's theorem to any category with finite products in the following way:[8] let be such a category, and let be a terminal object in . Suppose that is an object in and that there exists an endomorphism that does not have any fixed points; that is, there is no morphism that satisfies . Then there is no object of such that a morphism can parameterize all morphisms . In other words, for every object and every morphism , an attempt to write maps as maps of the form must leave out at least one map .
See also
- Schröder–Bernstein theorem
- Cantor's first uncountability proof
- Controversy over Cantor's theory
References
- ^ ISBN 978-1-4614-8854-5.
- ^ a b Lawrence Paulson (1992). Set Theory as a Computational Logic (PDF). University of Cambridge Computer Laboratory. p. 14.
- ^ ISBN 978-0-19-925405-7.
- ^ ISBN 978-3-540-49553-6.
- ISBN 978-0-8218-7360-1. Also published in International Logic Review 15 pp. 11−23.
- ^ Cantor, Georg (1891), "Über eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigskeitslehre", Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung (in German), 1: 75–78, also in Georg Cantor, Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, E. Zermelo, 1932.
- ^ A. Kanamori, "The Empty Set, the Singleton, and the Ordered Pair", p.276. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic vol. 9, no. 3, (2003). Accessed 21 August 2023.
- ISBN 978-0-521-89485-2.
- ISBN 978-1-61427-131-4(Paperback edition).
- ISBN 3-540-44085-2