Term logic
This article may need to be rewritten to comply with Wikipedia's quality standards. (January 2023) |
In
.Term logic revived in
However, even if eclipsed by newer logical systems, term logic still plays a significant role in the study of logic. Rather than radically breaking with term logic, modern logics typically expand it.
Aristotle's system
The Prior Analytics represents the first formal study of logic, where logic is understood as the study of arguments. An argument is a series of true or false statements which lead to a true or false conclusion. of a syllogism is a categorical sentence which has a subject and a predicate connected by a verb. The usual way of connecting the subject and predicate of a categorical sentence as Aristotle does in On Interpretation is by using a linking verb e.g. P is S. However, in the Prior Analytics Aristotle rejects the usual form in favour of three of his inventions:
- P belongs to S
- P is predicated of S
- P is said of S
Aristotle does not explain why he introduces these innovative expressions but scholars conjecture that the reason may have been that it facilitates the use of letters instead of terms avoiding the ambiguity that results in Greek when letters are used with the linking verb.[6] In his formulation of syllogistic propositions, instead of the copula ("All/some... are/are not..."), Aristotle uses the expression, "... belongs to/does not belong to all/some..." or "... is said/is not said of all/some..."[7] There are four different types of categorical sentences: universal affirmative (A), universal negative (E), particular affirmative (I) and particular negative (O).
- A - A belongs to every B
- E - A belongs to no B
- I - A belongs to some B
- O - A does not belong to some B
A method of symbolization that originated and was used in the Middle Ages greatly simplifies the study of the Prior Analytics. Following this tradition then, let:
- a = belongs to every
- e = belongs to no
- i = belongs to some
- o = does not belong to some
Categorical sentences may then be abbreviated as follows:
- AaB = A belongs to every B (Every B is A)
- AeB = A belongs to no B (No B is A)
- AiB = A belongs to some B (Some B is A)
- AoB = A does not belong to some B (Some B is not A)
From the viewpoint of modern logic, only a few types of sentences can be represented in this way.[8]
Basics
The fundamental assumption behind the theory is that the
- The term is a part of speech representing something, but which is not true or false in its own right, such as "man" or "mortal". As originally conceived, all terms would be drawn from one of ten categories enumerated by Aristotle in his Organon, classifying all objects and qualities within the domain of logical discourse.
- The formal model of proposition consists of two terms, one of which, the "predicate", is "affirmed" or "denied" of the other, the "subject", and which is capable of truth or falsity.
- The syllogism is an inference in which one proposition (the "conclusion") follows of necessity from two other propositions (the "premises").
A proposition may be universal or particular, and it may be affirmative or negative. Traditionally, the four kinds of propositions are:
- A-type: Universal and affirmative ("All philosophers are mortal")
- E-type: Universal and negative ("All philosophers are not mortal")
- I-type: Particular and affirmative ("Some philosophers are mortal")
- O-type: Particular and negative ("Some philosophers are not mortal")
This was called the fourfold scheme of propositions (see types of syllogism for an explanation of the letters A, I, E, and O in the traditional square). Aristotle's original square of opposition, however, does not lack existential import.
Term
A term (Greek ὅρος horos) is the basic component of the proposition. The original meaning of the horos (and also of the Latin terminus) is "extreme" or "boundary". The two terms lie on the outside of the proposition, joined by the act of affirmation or denial.
For early modern
Proposition
In term logic, a "proposition" is simply a form of language: a particular kind of
However, as in modern philosophical logic, it means that which is asserted by the sentence. Writers before
The logical quality of a proposition is whether it is affirmative (the predicate is affirmed of the subject) or negative (the predicate is denied of the subject). Thus every philosopher is mortal is affirmative, since the mortality of philosophers is affirmed universally, whereas no philosopher is mortal is negative by denying such mortality in particular.
The quantity of a proposition is whether it is universal (the predicate is affirmed or denied of all subjects or of "the whole") or particular (the predicate is affirmed or denied of some subject or a "part" thereof). In case where
Singular terms
For Aristotle, the distinction between singular[
He contrasts universal (katholou)[9] secondary substance, genera, with primary substance, particular (kath' hekaston)[9][10] specimens. The formal nature of universals, in so far as they can be generalized "always, or for the most part", is the subject matter of both scientific study and formal logic.[11]
The essential feature of the syllogism is that, of the four terms in the two premises, one must occur twice. Thus
- All Greeks are men
- All men are mortal.
The subject of one premise, must be the predicate of the other, and so it is necessary to eliminate from the logic any terms which cannot function both as subject and predicate, namely singular terms.
However, in a popular 17th-century version of the syllogism, Port-Royal Logic, singular terms were treated as universals:[12]
- All men are mortals
- All Socrates are men
- All Socrates are mortals
This is clearly awkward, a weakness exploited by Frege in his devastating attack on the system.
The famous syllogism "Socrates is a man ...", is frequently quoted as though from Aristotle,[13] but in fact, it is nowhere in the Organon. Sextus Empiricus in his Hyp. Pyrrh (Outlines of Pyrronism) ii. 164 first mentions the related syllogism "Socrates is a human being, Every human being is an animal, Therefore, Socrates is an animal."
The three figures
Depending on the position of the middle term, Aristotle divides the syllogism into three kinds: syllogism in the first, second, and third figure.[14] If the Middle Term is subject of one premise and predicate of the other, the premises are in the First Figure. If the Middle Term is predicate of both premises, the premises are in the Second Figure. If the Middle Term is subject of both premises, the premises are in the Third Figure.[15]
Symbolically, the Three Figures may be represented as follows:[16]
First figure | Second figure | Third figure | |
---|---|---|---|
Predicate — Subject | Predicate — Subject | Predicate — Subject | |
Major premise | A ------------ B | B ------------ A | A ------------ B |
Minor premise | B ------------ C | B ------------ C | C ------------ B |
Conclusion | A ********** C | A ********** C | A ********** C |
The fourth figure
In Aristotelian syllogistic (Prior Analytics, Bk I Caps 4-7), syllogisms are divided into three figures according to the position of the middle term in the two premises. The fourth figure, in which the middle term is the predicate in the major premise and the subject in the minor, was added by Aristotle's pupil Theophrastus and does not occur in Aristotle's work, although there is evidence that Aristotle knew of fourth-figure syllogisms.[17]
Syllogism in the first figure
In the Prior Analytics translated by A. J. Jenkins as it appears in volume 8 of the Great Books of the Western World, Aristotle says of the First Figure: "... If A is predicated of all B, and B of all C, A must be predicated of all C."[18] In the Prior Analytics translated by Robin Smith, Aristotle says of the first figure: "... For if A is predicated of every B and B of every C, it is necessary for A to be predicated of every C."[19]
Taking a = is predicated of all = is predicated of every, and using the symbolical method used in the Middle Ages, then the first figure is simplified to:[20]
- If AaB
- and BaC
- then AaC.
Or what amounts to the same thing:
- AaB, BaC; therefore AaC
When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the first figure, Aristotle comes up with the following valid forms of deduction for the first figure:
- AaB, BaC; therefore, AaC
- AeB, BaC; therefore, AeC
- AaB, BiC; therefore, AiC
- AeB, BiC; therefore, AoC
In the Middle Ages, for mnemonic reasons they were called "Barbara", "Celarent", "Darii" and "Ferio" respectively.[21]
The difference between the first figure and the other two figures is that the syllogism of the first figure is complete while that of the second and third is not. This is important in Aristotle's theory of the syllogism for the first figure is axiomatic while the second and third require proof. The proof of the second and third figure always leads back to the first figure.[22]
Syllogism in the second figure
This is what Robin Smith says in English that Aristotle said in Ancient Greek: "... If M belongs to every N but to no X, then neither will N belong to any X. For if M belongs to no X, neither does X belong to any M; but M belonged to every N; therefore, X will belong to no N (for the first figure has again come about)."[23]
The above statement can be simplified by using the symbolical method used in the Middle Ages:
- If MaN
- but MeX
- then NeX.
- For if MeX
- then XeM
- but MaN
- therefore XeN.
When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the second figure, Aristotle comes up with the following valid forms of deduction for the second figure:
- MaN, MeX; therefore NeX
- MeN, MaX; therefore NeX
- MeN, MiX; therefore NoX
- MaN, MoX; therefore NoX
In the Middle Ages, for mnemonic reasons they were called respectively "Camestres", "Cesare", "Festino" and "Baroco".[24]
Syllogism in the third figure
Aristotle says in the Prior Analytics, "... If one term belongs to all and another to none of the same thing, or if they both belong to all or none of it, I call such figure the third." Referring to universal terms, "... then when both P and R belongs to every S, it results of necessity that P will belong to some R."[25]
Simplifying:
- If PaS
- and RaS
- then PiR.
When the four syllogistic propositions, a, e, i, o are placed in the third figure, Aristotle develops six more valid forms of deduction:
- PaS, RaS; therefore PiR
- PeS, RaS; therefore PoR
- PiS, RaS; therefore PiR
- PaS, RiS; therefore PiR
- PoS, RaS; therefore PoR
- PeS, RiS; therefore PoR
In the Middle Ages, for mnemonic reasons, these six forms were called respectively: "Darapti", "Felapton", "Disamis", "Datisi", "Bocardo" and "Ferison".[26]
Table of syllogisms
Figure | Major premise | Minor premise | Conclusion | Mnemonic name |
---|---|---|---|---|
First Figure | AaB | BaC | AaC | Barbara |
AeB | BaC | AeC | Celarent | |
AaB | BiC | AiC | Darii | |
AeB | BiC | AoC | Ferio | |
Second Figure | MaN | MeX | NeX | Camestres |
MeN | MaX | NeX | Cesare | |
MeN | MiX | NoX | Festino | |
MaN | MoX | NoX | Baroco | |
Third Figure | PaS | RaS | PiR | Darapti |
PeS | RaS | PoR | Felapton | |
PiS | RaS | PiR | Disamis | |
PaS | RiS | PiR | Datisi | |
PoS | RaS | PoR | Bocardo | |
PeS | RiS | PoR | Ferison |
Decline of term logic
Term logic began to decline in
19th-century attempts to algebraize logic, such as the work of
Term logic also survived to some extent in traditional
]Revival
Some philosophers have complained that predicate logic:
- Is unnatural in a sense, in that its syntax does not follow the syntax of the sentences that figure in our everyday reasoning. It is, as bound variable.
- Suffers from theoretical problems, probably the most serious being empty names and identity statements.
Even academic philosophers entirely in the mainstream, such as Gareth Evans, have written as follows:
- "I come to logical constants... The objection would not be that such [Fregean] truth conditions are not correct, but that, in a sense which we would all dearly love to have more exactly explained, the syntactic shape of the sentence is treated as so much misleading surface structure" (Evans 1977)
Boole’s acceptance of Aristotle
George Boole's unwavering acceptance of Aristotle's logic is emphasized by the historian of logic John Corcoran in an accessible introduction to Laws of Thought[29] Corcoran also wrote a point-by-point comparison of Prior Analytics and Laws of Thought.[30] According to Corcoran, Boole fully accepted and endorsed Aristotle's logic. Boole's goals were “to go under, over, and beyond” Aristotle's logic by:
- providing it with mathematical foundations involving equations;
- extending the class of problems it could treat– from assessing validity to solving equations; and
- expanding the range of applications it could handle– e.g. from propositions having only two terms to those having arbitrarily many.
More specifically, Boole agreed with what
See also
Notes
- ^ Degnan, M. 1994. Recent Work in Aristotle's Logic. Philosophical Books 35.2 (April, 1994): 81-89.
- ISBN 978-0-19-925041-7." in the Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 2010.02.02.
- ISBN 0-07-053628-7.
- ^ Robin Smith. Aristotle: Prior Analytics. p. XVII.
- ^ John Nolt/Dennis Rohatyn. Logic: Schaum's Outline of Theory and Problems. pp. 274–275.
- ISBN 978-1-4051-2223-8.
- ISBN 978-90-277-0030-8.
- ^ The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. pp. 34–35.
- ^ Perseus Project.
- ^ καθ' ἕκαστον in Liddell and Scott.
- ^ They are mentioned briefly in the De Interpretatione. Afterwards, in the chapters of the Prior Analytics where Aristotle methodically sets out his theory of the syllogism, they are entirely ignored.
- ^ Arnauld, Antoine and Nicole, Pierre; (1662) La logique, ou l'art de penser. Part 2, chapter 3
- ^ For example: Kapp, Greek Foundations of Traditional Logic, New York 1942, p. 17, Copleston A History of Philosophy Vol. I., p. 277, Russell, A History of Western Philosophy London 1946 p. 218.
- ^ The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. p. 35.
At the foundation of Aristotle's syllogistic is a theory of a specific class of arguments: arguments having as premises exactly two categorical sentences with one term in common.
- ^ Robin Smith. Aristotle: Prior Analytics. p. XVIII.
- ^ Henrik Legerlund. Modal Syllogistics in the Middle Ages. p. 4.
- ISBN 978-0-04-920067-8.
- ^ Great Books of the Western World. Vol. 8. p. 40.
- ^ Robin Smith. Aristotle: Prior Analytics. p. 4.
- ^ The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. p. 41.
- ^ The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. p. 41.
- ^ Henrik Legerlund. Modal Syllogistics in the Middle Ages. p. 6.
- ^ Robin Smith. Aristotle: Prior Analytics. p. 7.
- ^ The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. p. 41.
- ^ Robin Smith. Aristotle: Prior Analytics. p. 9.
- ^ The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. p. 41.
- ^ The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. p. 41.
- ^ Copleston's A History of Philosophy
- ^ George Boole. 1854/2003. The Laws of Thought, facsimile of 1854 edition, with an introduction by J. Corcoran. Buffalo: Prometheus Books (2003). Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review.24 (2004) 167–169.
- ^ John Corcoran, Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought, History and Philosophy of Logic, vol. 24 (2003), pp. 261–288.
References
- Bochenski, I. M., 1951. Ancient Formal Logic. North-Holland.
- Louis Couturat, 1961 (1901). La Logique de Leibniz. Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlagsbuchhandlung.
- Gareth Evans, 1977, "Pronouns, Quantifiers and Relative Clauses," Canadian Journal of Philosophy.
- Peter Geach, 1976. Reason and Argument. University of California Press.
- Hammond and Scullard, 1992. The Oxford Classical Dictionary. Oxford University Press, ISBN 0-19-869117-3.
- Joyce, George Hayward, 1949 (1908). Principles of Logic, 3rd ed. Longmans. A manual written for use in Catholic seminaries. Authoritative on traditional logic, with many references to medieval and ancient sources. Contains no hint of modern formal logic. The author lived 1864–1943.
- Jan Łukasiewicz, 1951. Aristotle's Syllogistic, from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic. Oxford Univ. Press.
- William Calvert Kneale and Martha Kneale, 1962. The Development of Logic. Oxford [England] Clarendon Press. Reviews Aristotelean logic and its influences up to modern times.
- Pratt-Hartmann, Ian (2023-03-30). Fragments of First-Order Logic. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-196006-2.. Chapter 2 presents a modern overview, with a bibliography.
- John Stuart Mill, 1904. A System of Logic, 8th ed. London.
- Parry and Hacker, 1991. Aristotelian Logic. State University of New York Press.
- Arthur Prior
- 1962: Formal Logic, 2nd ed. Oxford Univ. Press. While primarily devoted to modern formal logic, contains much on term and medieval logic.
- 1976: The Doctrine of Propositions and Terms. Peter Geach and A. J. P. Kenny, eds. London: Duckworth.
- Willard Quine, 1986. Philosophy of Logic 2nd ed. Harvard Univ. Press.
- Rose, Lynn E., 1968. Aristotle's Syllogistic. Springfield: Clarence C. Thomas.
- Sommers, Fred
- 1970: "The Calculus of Terms," Mind 79: 1-39. Reprinted in Englebretsen, G., ed., 1987. The new syllogistic New York: Peter Lang. ISBN 0-8204-0448-9
- 1982: The logic of natural language. Oxford University Press.
- 1990: "Predication in the Logic of Terms," Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 31: 106–26.
- and Englebretsen, George, 2000: An invitation to formal reasoning. The logic of terms. Aldershot UK: Ashgate. ISBN 0-7546-1366-6.
- 1970: "The Calculus of Terms," Mind 79: 1-39. Reprinted in Englebretsen, G., ed., 1987. The new syllogistic New York: Peter Lang.
- Szabolcsi Lorne, 2008. Numerical Term Logic. Lewiston: Edwin Mellen Press.
External links
- Term logic at PhilPapers
- Smith, Robin. "Aristotle's Logic". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- "Term logic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Aristotle's term logic online-This online program provides a platform for experimentation and research on Aristotelian logic.
- Annotated bibliographies:
- PlanetMath: Aristotelian Logic.
- Interactive Syllogistic Machine for Term Logic A web based syllogistic machine for exploring fallacies, figures, terms, and modes of syllogisms.