Surjective function

Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.

In

unique
; the function f may map one or more elements of X to the same element of Y.

The term surjective and the related terms

bijective were introduced by Nicolas Bourbaki,[3][4] a group of mainly French 20th-century mathematicians who, under this pseudonym, wrote a series of books presenting an exposition of modern advanced mathematics, beginning in 1935. The French word sur means over or above, and relates to the fact that the image
of the domain of a surjective function completely covers the function's codomain.

Any function induces a surjection by

restricting its codomain to the image of its domain. Every surjective function has a right inverse assuming the axiom of choice, and every function with a right inverse is necessarily a surjection. The composition
of surjective functions is always surjective. Any function can be decomposed into a surjection and an injection.

Definition

A surjective function is a function whose image is equal to its codomain. Equivalently, a function with domain and codomain is surjective if for every in there exists at least one in with .[1] Surjections are sometimes denoted by a two-headed rightwards arrow (U+21A0 RIGHTWARDS TWO HEADED ARROW),[5] as in .

Symbolically,

If , then is said to be surjective if
.[2][6]

Examples

A non-surjective function from domain X to codomain Y. The smaller yellow oval inside Y is the image (also called range) of f. This function is not surjective, because the image does not fill the whole codomain. In other words, Y is colored in a two-step process: First, for every x in X, the point f(x) is colored yellow; Second, all the rest of the points in Y, that are not yellow, are colored blue. The function f would be surjective only if there were no blue points.

Properties

A function is

bijective if and only if it is both surjective and injective
.

If (as is often done) a function is identified with its graph, then surjectivity is not a property of the function itself, but rather a property of the mapping.[7] This is, the function together with its codomain. Unlike injectivity, surjectivity cannot be read off of the graph of the function alone.

Surjections as right invertible functions

The function g : YX is said to be a right inverse of the function f : XY if f(g(y)) = y for every y in Y (g can be undone by f). In other words, g is a right inverse of f if the composition f o g of g and f in that order is the identity function on the domain Y of g. The function g need not be a complete inverse of f because the composition in the other order, g o f, may not be the identity function on the domain X of f. In other words, f can undo or "reverse" g, but cannot necessarily be reversed by it.

Every function with a right inverse is necessarily a surjection. The proposition that every surjective function has a right inverse is equivalent to the axiom of choice.

If f : XY is surjective and B is a

preimage
f −1(B).

For example, in the first illustration in the gallery, there is some function g such that g(C) = 4. There is also some function f such that f(4) = C. It doesn't matter that g is not unique (it would also work if g(C) equals 3); it only matters that f "reverses" g.

Surjections as epimorphisms

A function f : XY is surjective if and only if it is

right-cancellative:[8] given any functions g,h : YZ, whenever g o f = h o f, then g = h. This property is formulated in terms of functions and their composition and can be generalized to the more general notion of the morphisms of a category and their composition. Right-cancellative morphisms are called epimorphisms. Specifically, surjective functions are precisely the epimorphisms in the category of sets
. The prefix epi is derived from the Greek preposition ἐπί meaning over, above, on.

Any morphism with a right inverse is an epimorphism, but the converse is not true in general. A right inverse g of a morphism f is called a

split epimorphism
.

Surjections as binary relations

Any function with domain X and codomain Y can be seen as a

right-total
.

Cardinality of the domain of a surjection

The cardinality of the domain of a surjective function is greater than or equal to the cardinality of its codomain: If f : XY is a surjective function, then X has at least as many elements as Y, in the sense of cardinal numbers. (The proof appeals to the axiom of choice to show that a function g : YX satisfying f(g(y)) = y for all y in Y exists. g is easily seen to be injective, thus the formal definition of |Y| ≤ |X| is satisfied.)

Specifically, if both X and Y are

injective
.

Given two sets X and Y, the notation X* Y is used to say that either X is empty or that there is a surjection from Y onto X. Using the axiom of choice one can show that X* Y and Y* X together imply that |Y| = |X|, a variant of the Schröder–Bernstein theorem.

Composition and decomposition

The composition of surjective functions is always surjective: If f and g are both surjective, and the codomain of g is equal to the domain of f, then f o g is surjective. Conversely, if f o g is surjective, then f is surjective (but g, the function applied first, need not be). These properties generalize from surjections in the category of sets to any epimorphisms in any category.

Any function can be decomposed into a surjection and an

preimages h−1(z) where z is in h(X). These preimages are disjoint and partition
X. Then f carries each x to the element of Y which contains it, and g carries each element of Y to the point in Z to which h sends its points. Then f is surjective since it is a projection map, and g is injective by definition.

Induced surjection and induced bijection

Any function induces a surjection by restricting its codomain to its range. Any surjective function induces a bijection defined on a

projection map
which sends each x in A to its equivalence class [x]~, and let fP : A/~ → B be the well-defined function given by fP([x]~) = f(x). Then f = fP o P(~).

The set of surjections

Given fixed A and B, one can form the set of surjections AB. The cardinality of this set is one of the twelve aspects of Rota's Twelvefold way, and is given by , where denotes a Stirling number of the second kind.

Gallery

  • Surjective composition: the first function need not be surjective.
    Surjective composition: the first function need not be surjective.
  • Non-surjective functions in the Cartesian plane. Although some parts of the function are surjective, where elements y in Y do have a value x in X such that y = f(x), some parts are not. Left: There is y0 in Y, but there is no x0 in X such that y0 = f(x0). Right: There are y1, y2 and y3 in Y, but there are no x1, x2, and x3 in X such that y1 = f(x1), y2 = f(x2), and y3 = f(x3).
  • Interpretation for surjective functions in the Cartesian plane, defined by the mapping f : XY, where y = f(x), X = domain of function, Y = range of function. Every element in the range is mapped onto from an element in the domain, by the rule f. There may be a number of domain elements which map to the same range element. That is, every y in Y is mapped from an element x in X, more than one x can map to the same y. Left: Only one domain is shown which makes f surjective. Right: two possible domains X1 and X2 are shown.

See also

References

  1. ^ a b "Injective, Surjective and Bijective". www.mathsisfun.com. Retrieved 2019-12-07.
  2. ^ a b "Bijection, Injection, And Surjection | Brilliant Math & Science Wiki". brilliant.org. Retrieved 2019-12-07.
  3. ^ Miller, Jeff, "Injection, Surjection and Bijection", Earliest Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics, Tripod.
  4. .
  5. ^ "Arrows – Unicode" (PDF). Retrieved 2013-05-11.
  6. ^ Farlow, S. J. "Injections, Surjections, and Bijections" (PDF). math.umaine.edu. Retrieved 2019-12-06.
  7. ^ T. M. Apostol (1981). Mathematical Analysis. Addison-Wesley. p. 35.
  8. . Retrieved 2009-11-25.

Further reading