Mathematical logic
Part of a series on | ||
Mathematics | ||
---|---|---|
|
||
Mathematics Portal | ||
Mathematical logic is the study of
Since its inception, mathematical logic has both contributed to and been motivated by the study of foundations of mathematics. This study began in the late 19th century with the development of axiomatic frameworks for geometry, arithmetic, and analysis. In the early 20th century it was shaped by David Hilbert's program to prove the consistency of foundational theories. Results of Kurt Gödel, Gerhard Gentzen, and others provided partial resolution to the program, and clarified the issues involved in proving consistency. Work in set theory showed that almost all ordinary mathematics can be formalized in terms of sets, although there are some theorems that cannot be proven in common axiom systems for set theory. Contemporary work in the foundations of mathematics often focuses on establishing which parts of mathematics can be formalized in particular formal systems (as in reverse mathematics) rather than trying to find theories in which all of mathematics can be developed.
Subfields and scope
The Handbook of Mathematical Logic[1] in 1977 makes a rough division of contemporary mathematical logic into four areas:
- set theory
- model theory
- recursion theory, and
- constructive mathematics(considered as parts of a single area).
Additionally, sometimes the field of
The mathematical field of category theory uses many formal axiomatic methods, and includes the study of categorical logic, but category theory is not ordinarily considered a subfield of mathematical logic. Because of its applicability in diverse fields of mathematics, mathematicians including Saunders Mac Lane have proposed category theory as a foundational system for mathematics, independent of set theory. These foundations use toposes, which resemble generalized models of set theory that may employ classical or nonclassical logic.
History
Mathematical logic emerged in the mid-19th century as a subfield of mathematics, reflecting the confluence of two traditions: formal philosophical logic and mathematics.[3] Mathematical logic, also called 'logistic', 'symbolic logic', the 'algebra of logic', and, more recently, simply 'formal logic', is the set of logical theories elaborated in the course of the nineteenth century with the aid of an artificial notation and a rigorously deductive method.[4] Before this emergence, logic was studied with rhetoric, with calculationes,[5] through the syllogism, and with philosophy. The first half of the 20th century saw an explosion of fundamental results, accompanied by vigorous debate over the foundations of mathematics.
Early history
Theories of logic were developed in many cultures in history, including
19th century
In the middle of the nineteenth century,
Gottlob Frege presented an independent development of logic with quantifiers in his Begriffsschrift, published in 1879, a work generally considered as marking a turning point in the history of logic. Frege's work remained obscure, however, until Bertrand Russell began to promote it near the turn of the century. The two-dimensional notation Frege developed was never widely adopted and is unused in contemporary texts.
From 1890 to 1905, Ernst Schröder published Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik in three volumes. This work summarized and extended the work of Boole, De Morgan, and Peirce, and was a comprehensive reference to symbolic logic as it was understood at the end of the 19th century.
Foundational theories
Concerns that mathematics had not been built on a proper foundation led to the development of axiomatic systems for fundamental areas of mathematics such as arithmetic, analysis, and geometry.
In logic, the term arithmetic refers to the theory of the natural numbers. Giuseppe Peano[9] published a set of axioms for arithmetic that came to bear his name (Peano axioms), using a variation of the logical system of Boole and Schröder but adding quantifiers. Peano was unaware of Frege's work at the time. Around the same time Richard Dedekind showed that the natural numbers are uniquely characterized by their induction properties. Dedekind proposed a different characterization, which lacked the formal logical character of Peano's axioms.[10] Dedekind's work, however, proved theorems inaccessible in Peano's system, including the uniqueness of the set of natural numbers (up to isomorphism) and the recursive definitions of addition and multiplication from the successor function and mathematical induction.
In the mid-19th century, flaws in Euclid's axioms for geometry became known.
The 19th century saw great advances in the theory of
but remained relatively unknown.20th century
In the early decades of the 20th century, the main areas of study were set theory and formal logic. The discovery of paradoxes in informal set theory caused some to wonder whether mathematics itself is inconsistent, and to look for proofs of consistency.
In 1900, Hilbert posed a famous list of 23 problems for the next century. The first two of these were to resolve the continuum hypothesis and prove the consistency of elementary arithmetic, respectively; the tenth was to produce a method that could decide whether a multivariate polynomial equation over the integers has a solution. Subsequent work to resolve these problems shaped the direction of mathematical logic, as did the effort to resolve Hilbert's Entscheidungsproblem, posed in 1928. This problem asked for a procedure that would decide, given a formalized mathematical statement, whether the statement is true or false.
Set theory and paradoxes
Ernst Zermelo gave a proof that every set could be well-ordered, a result Georg Cantor had been unable to obtain.[19] To achieve the proof, Zermelo introduced the axiom of choice, which drew heated debate and research among mathematicians and the pioneers of set theory. The immediate criticism of the method led Zermelo to publish a second exposition of his result, directly addressing criticisms of his proof.[20] This paper led to the general acceptance of the axiom of choice in the mathematics community.
Skepticism about the axiom of choice was reinforced by recently discovered paradoxes in naive set theory. Cesare Burali-Forti[21] was the first to state a paradox: the Burali-Forti paradox shows that the collection of all ordinal numbers cannot form a set. Very soon thereafter, Bertrand Russell discovered Russell's paradox in 1901, and Jules Richard discovered Richard's paradox.[22]
Zermelo provided the first set of axioms for set theory.
In 1910, the first volume of Principia Mathematica by Russell and Alfred North Whitehead was published. This seminal work developed the theory of functions and cardinality in a completely formal framework of type theory, which Russell and Whitehead developed in an effort to avoid the paradoxes. Principia Mathematica is considered one of the most influential works of the 20th century, although the framework of type theory did not prove popular as a foundational theory for mathematics.[24]
Fraenkel
Symbolic logic
In his doctoral thesis,
In 1931, Gödel published
Gödel's theorem shows that a
The first textbook on symbolic logic for the layman was written by Lewis Carroll,[33] author of Alice's Adventures in Wonderland, in 1896.[34]
Beginnings of the other branches
Alfred Tarski developed the basics of model theory.
Beginning in 1935, a group of prominent mathematicians collaborated under the pseudonym
The study of computability came to be known as recursion theory or computability theory, because early formalizations by Gödel and Kleene relied on recursive definitions of functions.[b] When these definitions were shown equivalent to Turing's formalization involving Turing machines, it became clear that a new concept – the computable function – had been discovered, and that this definition was robust enough to admit numerous independent characterizations. In his work on the incompleteness theorems in 1931, Gödel lacked a rigorous concept of an effective formal system; he immediately realized that the new definitions of computability could be used for this purpose, allowing him to state the incompleteness theorems in generality that could only be implied in the original paper.
Numerous results in recursion theory were obtained in the 1940s by Stephen Cole Kleene and Emil Leon Post. Kleene[35] introduced the concepts of relative computability, foreshadowed by Turing,[36] and the arithmetical hierarchy. Kleene later generalized recursion theory to higher-order functionals. Kleene and Georg Kreisel studied formal versions of intuitionistic mathematics, particularly in the context of proof theory.
Formal logical systems
Logical connectives | ||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
|
||||||||||||||||||||||
Related concepts | ||||||||||||||||||||||
Applications | ||||||||||||||||||||||
Category | ||||||||||||||||||||||
At its core, mathematical logic deals with mathematical concepts expressed using
First-order logic
First-order logic is a particular
Early results from formal logic established limitations of first-order logic. The Löwenheim–Skolem theorem (1919) showed that if a set of sentences in a countable first-order language has an infinite model then it has at least one model of each infinite cardinality. This shows that it is impossible for a set of first-order axioms to characterize the natural numbers, the real numbers, or any other infinite structure up to isomorphism. As the goal of early foundational studies was to produce axiomatic theories for all parts of mathematics, this limitation was particularly stark.
Gödel's completeness theorem established the equivalence between semantic and syntactic definitions of logical consequence in first-order logic.[30] It shows that if a particular sentence is true in every model that satisfies a particular set of axioms, then there must be a finite deduction of the sentence from the axioms. The compactness theorem first appeared as a lemma in Gödel's proof of the completeness theorem, and it took many years before logicians grasped its significance and began to apply it routinely. It says that a set of sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset has a model, or in other words that an inconsistent set of formulas must have a finite inconsistent subset. The completeness and compactness theorems allow for sophisticated analysis of logical consequence in first-order logic and the development of model theory, and they are a key reason for the prominence of first-order logic in mathematics.
Gödel's incompleteness theorems establish additional limits on first-order axiomatizations.[37] The first incompleteness theorem states that for any consistent, effectively given (defined below) logical system that is capable of interpreting arithmetic, there exists a statement that is true (in the sense that it holds for the natural numbers) but not provable within that logical system (and which indeed may fail in some non-standard models of arithmetic which may be consistent with the logical system). For example, in every logical system capable of expressing the Peano axioms, the Gödel sentence holds for the natural numbers but cannot be proved.
Here a logical system is said to be effectively given if it is possible to decide, given any formula in the language of the system, whether the formula is an axiom, and one which can express the Peano axioms is called "sufficiently strong." When applied to first-order logic, the first incompleteness theorem implies that any sufficiently strong, consistent, effective first-order theory has models that are not
Other classical logics
Many logics besides first-order logic are studied. These include
The most well studied infinitary logic is . In this logic, quantifiers may only be nested to finite depths, as in first-order logic, but formulas may have finite or countably infinite conjunctions and disjunctions within them. Thus, for example, it is possible to say that an object is a whole number using a formula of such as
Higher-order logics allow for quantification not only of elements of the domain of discourse, but subsets of the domain of discourse, sets of such subsets, and other objects of higher type. The semantics are defined so that, rather than having a separate domain for each higher-type quantifier to range over, the quantifiers instead range over all objects of the appropriate type. The logics studied before the development of first-order logic, for example Frege's logic, had similar set-theoretic aspects. Although higher-order logics are more expressive, allowing complete axiomatizations of structures such as the natural numbers, they do not satisfy analogues of the completeness and compactness theorems from first-order logic, and are thus less amenable to proof-theoretic analysis.
Another type of logics are fixed-point logics that allow
One can formally define an extension of first-order logic — a notion which encompasses all logics in this section because they behave like first-order logic in certain fundamental ways, but does not encompass all logics in general, e.g. it does not encompass intuitionistic, modal or fuzzy logic.
Lindström's theorem implies that the only extension of first-order logic satisfying both the compactness theorem and the downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is first-order logic.
Nonclassical and modal logic
Modal logics include additional modal operators, such as an operator which states that a particular formula is not only true, but necessarily true. Although modal logic is not often used to axiomatize mathematics, it has been used to study the properties of first-order provability[38] and set-theoretic forcing.[39]
Algebraic logic
Algebraic logic uses the methods of abstract algebra to study the semantics of formal logics. A fundamental example is the use of Boolean algebras to represent truth values in classical propositional logic, and the use of Heyting algebras to represent truth values in intuitionistic propositional logic. Stronger logics, such as first-order logic and higher-order logic, are studied using more complicated algebraic structures such as cylindric algebras.
Set theory
Set theory is the study of sets, which are abstract collections of objects. Many of the basic notions, such as ordinal and cardinal numbers, were developed informally by Cantor before formal axiomatizations of set theory were developed. The first such axiomatization, due to Zermelo,[23] was extended slightly to become Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF), which is now the most widely used foundational theory for mathematics.
Other formalizations of set theory have been proposed, including von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG), Morse–Kelley set theory (MK), and New Foundations (NF). Of these, ZF, NBG, and MK are similar in describing a cumulative hierarchy of sets. New Foundations takes a different approach; it allows objects such as the set of all sets at the cost of restrictions on its set-existence axioms. The system of Kripke–Platek set theory is closely related to generalized recursion theory.
Two famous statements in set theory are the axiom of choice and the continuum hypothesis. The axiom of choice, first stated by Zermelo,[19] was proved independent of ZF by Fraenkel,[25] but has come to be widely accepted by mathematicians. It states that given a collection of nonempty sets there is a single set C that contains exactly one element from each set in the collection. The set C is said to "choose" one element from each set in the collection. While the ability to make such a choice is considered obvious by some, since each set in the collection is nonempty, the lack of a general, concrete rule by which the choice can be made renders the axiom nonconstructive. Stefan Banach and Alfred Tarski showed that the axiom of choice can be used to decompose a solid ball into a finite number of pieces which can then be rearranged, with no scaling, to make two solid balls of the original size.[40] This theorem, known as the Banach–Tarski paradox, is one of many counterintuitive results of the axiom of choice.
The continuum hypothesis, first proposed as a conjecture by Cantor, was listed by David Hilbert as one of his 23 problems in 1900. Gödel showed that the continuum hypothesis cannot be disproven from the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (with or without the axiom of choice), by developing the constructible universe of set theory in which the continuum hypothesis must hold. In 1963, Paul Cohen showed that the continuum hypothesis cannot be proven from the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.[26] This independence result did not completely settle Hilbert's question, however, as it is possible that new axioms for set theory could resolve the hypothesis. Recent work along these lines has been conducted by W. Hugh Woodin, although its importance is not yet clear.[41]
Contemporary research in set theory includes the study of
Model theory
Model theory studies the models of various formal theories. Here a theory is a set of formulas in a particular formal logic and signature, while a model is a structure that gives a concrete interpretation of the theory. Model theory is closely related to universal algebra and algebraic geometry, although the methods of model theory focus more on logical considerations than those fields.
The set of all models of a particular theory is called an elementary class; classical model theory seeks to determine the properties of models in a particular elementary class, or determine whether certain classes of structures form elementary classes.
The method of
A trivial consequence of the continuum hypothesis is that a complete theory with less than continuum many nonisomorphic countable models can have only countably many. Vaught's conjecture, named after Robert Lawson Vaught, says that this is true even independently of the continuum hypothesis. Many special cases of this conjecture have been established.
Recursion theory
Classical recursion theory focuses on the computability of functions from the natural numbers to the natural numbers. The fundamental results establish a robust, canonical class of computable functions with numerous independent, equivalent characterizations using
Generalized recursion theory extends the ideas of recursion theory to computations that are no longer necessarily finite. It includes the study of computability in higher types as well as areas such as hyperarithmetical theory and α-recursion theory.
Contemporary research in recursion theory includes the study of applications such as
Algorithmically unsolvable problems
An important subfield of recursion theory studies algorithmic unsolvability; a decision problem or function problem is algorithmically unsolvable if there is no possible computable algorithm that returns the correct answer for all legal inputs to the problem. The first results about unsolvability, obtained independently by Church and Turing in 1936, showed that the Entscheidungsproblem is algorithmically unsolvable. Turing proved this by establishing the unsolvability of the halting problem, a result with far-ranging implications in both recursion theory and computer science.
There are many known examples of undecidable problems from ordinary mathematics. The word problem for groups was proved algorithmically unsolvable by Pyotr Novikov in 1955 and independently by W. Boone in 1959. The busy beaver problem, developed by Tibor Radó in 1962, is another well-known example.
Hilbert's tenth problem asked for an algorithm to determine whether a multivariate polynomial equation with integer coefficients has a solution in the integers. Partial progress was made by Julia Robinson, Martin Davis and Hilary Putnam. The algorithmic unsolvability of the problem was proved by Yuri Matiyasevich in 1970.[45]
Proof theory and constructive mathematics
The study of constructive mathematics, in the context of mathematical logic, includes the study of systems in non-classical logic such as intuitionistic logic, as well as the study of predicative systems. An early proponent of predicativism was Hermann Weyl, who showed it is possible to develop a large part of real analysis using only predicative methods.[46]
Because proofs are entirely finitary, whereas truth in a structure is not, it is common for work in constructive mathematics to emphasize provability. The relationship between provability in classical (or nonconstructive) systems and provability in intuitionistic (or constructive, respectively) systems is of particular interest. Results such as the
Recent developments in proof theory include the study of
Applications
"Mathematical logic has been successfully applied not only to mathematics and its foundations (
Connections with computer science
The study of
The theory of
Computer science also contributes to mathematics by developing techniques for the automatic checking or even finding of proofs, such as automated theorem proving and logic programming.
Descriptive complexity theory relates logics to computational complexity. The first significant result in this area, Fagin's theorem (1974) established that NP is precisely the set of languages expressible by sentences of existential second-order logic.
Foundations of mathematics
In the 19th century, mathematicians became aware of logical gaps and inconsistencies in their field. It was shown that Euclid's axioms for geometry, which had been taught for centuries as an example of the axiomatic method, were incomplete. The use of infinitesimals, and the very definition of function, came into question in analysis, as pathological examples such as Weierstrass' nowhere-differentiable continuous function were discovered.
Cantor's study of arbitrary infinite sets also drew criticism. Leopold Kronecker famously stated "God made the integers; all else is the work of man," endorsing a return to the study of finite, concrete objects in mathematics. Although Kronecker's argument was carried forward by constructivists in the 20th century, the mathematical community as a whole rejected them. David Hilbert argued in favor of the study of the infinite, saying "No one shall expel us from the Paradise that Cantor has created."
Mathematicians began to search for axiom systems that could be used to formalize large parts of mathematics. In addition to removing ambiguity from previously naive terms such as function, it was hoped that this axiomatization would allow for consistency proofs. In the 19th century, the main method of proving the consistency of a set of axioms was to provide a model for it. Thus, for example, non-Euclidean geometry can be proved consistent by defining point to mean a point on a fixed sphere and line to mean a great circle on the sphere. The resulting structure, a model of elliptic geometry, satisfies the axioms of plane geometry except the parallel postulate.
With the development of formal logic, Hilbert asked whether it would be possible to prove that an axiom system is consistent by analyzing the structure of possible proofs in the system, and showing through this analysis that it is impossible to prove a contradiction. This idea led to the study of proof theory. Moreover, Hilbert proposed that the analysis should be entirely concrete, using the term finitary to refer to the methods he would allow but not precisely defining them. This project, known as Hilbert's program, was seriously affected by Gödel's incompleteness theorems, which show that the consistency of formal theories of arithmetic cannot be established using methods formalizable in those theories. Gentzen showed that it is possible to produce a proof of the consistency of arithmetic in a finitary system augmented with axioms of transfinite induction, and the techniques he developed to do so were seminal in proof theory.
A second thread in the history of foundations of mathematics involves
In the early 20th century,
See also
- Argument
- Informal logic
- Universal logic
- Knowledge representation and reasoning
- Logic
- List of computability and complexity topics
- List of first-order theories
- List of logic symbols
- List of mathematical logic topics
- List of set theory topics
- Mereology
- Propositional calculus
- Well-formed formula
Notes
- ^ In the foreword to the 1934 first edition of "Grundlagen der Mathematik" (Hilbert & Bernays 1934), Bernays wrote the following, which is reminiscent of the famous note by Frege when informed of Russell's paradox.
Translation:"Die Ausführung dieses Vorhabens hat eine wesentliche Verzögerung dadurch erfahren, daß in einem Stadium, in dem die Darstellung schon ihrem Abschuß nahe war, durch das Erscheinen der Arbeiten von Herbrand und von Gödel eine veränderte Situation im Gebiet der Beweistheorie entstand, welche die Berücksichtigung neuer Einsichten zur Aufgabe machte. Dabei ist der Umfang des Buches angewachsen, so daß eine Teilung in zwei Bände angezeigt erschien."
So certainly Hilbert was aware of the importance of Gödel's work by 1934. The second volume in 1939 included a form of Gentzen's consistency proof for arithmetic."Carrying out this plan [by Hilbert for an exposition on proof theory for mathematical logic] has experienced an essential delay because, at the stage at which the exposition was already near to its conclusion, there occurred an altered situation in the area of proof theory due to the appearance of works by Herbrand and Gödel, which necessitated the consideration of new insights. Thus the scope of this book has grown, so that a division into two volumes seemed advisable."
- ^ A detailed study of this terminology is given by Soare 1996.
- ^ Ferreirós 2001 surveys the rise of first-order logic over other formal logics in the early 20th century.
References
- ^ Barwise (1989).
- ^ "Computability Theory and Foundations of Mathematics / February, 17th – 20th, 2014 / Tokyo Institute of Technology, Tokyo, Japan" (PDF).
- ^ Ferreirós (2001), p. 443.
- ^ Bochenski (1959), Sec. 0.1, p. 1.
- ^ Swineshead (1498).
- ^ Boehner (1950), p. xiv.
- ^ Katz (1998), p. 686.
- ^ "Bertić, Vatroslav | Hrvatska enciklopedija". www.enciklopedija.hr. Retrieved 2023-05-01.
- ^ Peano (1889).
- ^ Dedekind (1888).
- ^ Katz (1998), p. 774.
- ^ Lobachevsky (1840).
- ^ Hilbert (1899).
- ^ Pasch (1882).
- ^ Felscher (2000).
- ^ Dedekind (1872).
- ^ Cantor (1874).
- ^ Katz (1998), p. 807.
- ^ a b Zermelo (1904).
- ^ Zermelo (1908a).
- ^ Burali-Forti (1897).
- ^ Richard (1905).
- ^ a b Zermelo (1908b).
- ^ Ferreirós (2001), p. 445.
- ^ a b Fraenkel (1922).
- ^ a b Cohen (1966).
- ^ See also Cohen 2008.
- ^ Löwenheim (1915).
- ^ Skolem (1920).
- ^ a b Gödel (1929).
- ^ Gentzen (1936).
- ^ Gödel (1958).
- ^ Lewis Carroll: SYMBOLIC LOGIC Part I Elementary. pub. Macmillan 1896. Available online at: https://archive.org/details/symboliclogic00carr
- ^ Carroll (1896).
- ^ Kleene (1943).
- ^ Turing (1939).
- ^ Gödel (1931).
- ^ Solovay (1976).
- ^ Hamkins & Löwe (2007).
- ^ Banach & Tarski (1924).
- ^ Woodin (2001).
- ^ Tarski (1948).
- ^ Morley (1965).
- ^ Soare (2011).
- ^ Davis (1973).
- ^ Weyl 1918.
- ^ a b Bochenski (1959), Sec. 0.3, p. 2.
Undergraduate texts
- Walicki, Michał (2011). Introduction to Mathematical Logic. ISBN 9789814343879.
- ISBN 9780521007580.
- Crossley, J.N.; Ash, C.J.; Brickhill, C.J.; Stillwell, J.C.; Williams, N.H. (1972). What is mathematical logic?. London, Oxford, New York City: Zbl 0251.02001.
- Enderton, Herbert (2001). A mathematical introduction to logic (2nd ed.). ISBN 978-0-12-238452-3.
- Fisher, Alec (1982). Formal Number Theory and Computability: A Workbook. (suitable as a first course for independent study) (1st ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-853188-3.
- Hamilton, A.G. (1988). Logic for Mathematicians (2nd ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-36865-0.
- Ebbinghaus, H.-D.; Flum, J.; Thomas, W. (1994). Mathematical Logic (2nd ed.). ISBN 9780387942582.
- Katz, Robert (1964). Axiomatic Analysis. Boston MA: D. C. Heath and Company.
- ISBN 978-0-412-80830-2.
- ISBN 9781441912206.
- Schwichtenberg, Helmut (2003–2004). Mathematical Logic (PDF). Munich: Mathematisches Institut der Universität München. Retrieved 2016-02-24.
- Shawn Hedman, A first course in logic: an introduction to model theory, proof theory, computability, and complexity,
- van Dalen, Dirk (2013). Logic and Structure. Universitext. Berlin: ISBN 978-1-4471-4557-8.
Graduate texts
- Hinman, Peter G. (2005). Fundamentals of mathematical logic. A K Peters, Ltd. ISBN 1-56881-262-0.
- Andrews, Peter B. (2002). An Introduction to Mathematical Logic and Type Theory: To Truth Through Proof (2nd ed.). ISBN 978-1-4020-0763-7.
- ISBN 9780444863881.
- ISBN 9780521587136.
- ISBN 9783540440857.
- Kleene, Stephen Cole.(1952), Introduction to Metamathematics. New York: Van Nostrand. (Ishi Press: 2009 reprint).
- ISBN 0-486-42533-9.
- ISBN 9781568811352.
- ISBN 978-0-521-77911-1.
Research papers, monographs, texts, and surveys
- Augusto, Luis M. (2017). Logical consequences. Theory and applications: An introduction. London: College Publications. ISBN 978-1-84890-236-7.
- Boehner, Philotheus (1950). Medieval Logic. Manchester.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) - Cohen, Paul J. (1966). Set Theory and the Continuum Hypothesis. Menlo Park CA: W. A. Benjamin.
- ISBN 9780486469218.
- J.D. Sneed, The Logical Structure of Mathematical Physics. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1971 (revised edition 1979).
- ISBN 9780486614717.
- Felscher, Walter (2000). "Bolzano, Cauchy, Epsilon, Delta". The American Mathematical Monthly. 107 (9): 844–862. JSTOR 2695743.
- Ferreirós, José (2001). "The Road to Modern Logic-An Interpretation" (PDF). Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 7 (4): 441–484. S2CID 43258676.
- Hamkins, Joel David; Löwe, Benedikt (2007). "The modal logic of forcing". Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 360 (4): 1793–1818. S2CID 14724471.
- Katz, Victor J. (1998). A History of Mathematics. Addison–Wesley. ISBN 9780321016188.
- JSTOR 1994188.
- Soare, Robert I. (1996). "Computability and recursion". Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 2 (3): 284–321. S2CID 5894394.
- S2CID 121226261.
- Woodin, W. Hugh (2001). "The Continuum Hypothesis, Part I" (PDF). Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 48 (6).
Classical papers, texts, and collections
- .
Bochenski, Jozef Maria, ed. (1959). A Precis of Mathematical Logic. Synthese Library, Vol. 1. Translated by Otto Bird.
- Burali-Forti, Cesare (1897). A question on transfinite numbers. Reprinted in van Heijenoort 1976, pp. 104–111
Cantor, Georg (1874). "Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen" (PDF).
- Dedekind, Richard (1872). Stetigkeit und irrationale Zahlen (in German). English translation as: "Consistency and irrational numbers".
- Dedekind, Richard (1888). Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?. Two English translations:
- 1963 (1901). Essays on the Theory of Numbers. Beman, W. W., ed. and trans. Dover.
- 1996. In From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics, 2 vols, Ewald, William B., ed., Oxford University Press: 787–832.
- Fraenkel, Abraham A. (1922). "Der Begriff 'definit' und die Unabhängigkeit des Auswahlsaxioms". Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-mathematische Klasse (in German). pp. 253–257. Reprinted in English translation as "The notion of 'definite' and the independence of the axiom of choice" in van Heijenoort 1976, pp. 284–289.
- Frege, Gottlob (1879), Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle a. S.: Louis Nebert. Translation: Concept Script, a formal language of pure thought modelled upon that of arithmetic, by S. Bauer-Mengelberg in van Heijenoort 1976.
- Frege, Gottlob (1884), Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik: eine logisch-mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl. Breslau: W. Koebner. Translation: J. L. Austin, 1974. The Foundations of Arithmetic: A logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number, 2nd ed. Blackwell.
- S2CID 122719892. Reprinted in English translation in Gentzen's Collected works, M. E. Szabo, ed., North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1969.
- Gödel, Kurt (1929). Über die Vollständigkeit des Logikkalküls [Completeness of the logical calculus]. doctoral dissertation. University Of Vienna.
- S2CID 123343522.
- S2CID 197663120.
- doi:10.1111/j.1746-8361.1958.tb01464.x. Reprinted in English translation in Gödel's Collected Works, vol II, Solomon Fefermanet al., eds. Oxford University Press, 1993.
- ISBN 9780674324497. (pbk.).
- Hilbert, David (1899). Grundlagen der Geometrie (in German). Leipzig: Teubner. English 1902 edition (The Foundations of Geometry) republished 1980, Open Court, Chicago.
- S2CID 122870563. Lecture given at the International Congress of Mathematicians, 3 September 1928. Published in English translation as "The Grounding of Elementary Number Theory", in Mancosu 1998, pp. 266–273.
- MR 0237246.
- JSTOR 1990131.
- ISBN 0-486-60027-0.
- S2CID 116581304. Translated as "On possibilities in the calculus of relatives" in Jean van Heijenoort(1967). A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard Univ. Press. pp. 228–251.
- Mancosu, Paolo, ed. (1998). From Brouwer to Hilbert. The Debate on the Foundations of Mathematics in the 1920s. Oxford University Press.
- Pasch, Moritz (1882). Vorlesungen über neuere Geometrie.
- Peano, Giuseppe (1889). Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita (in Lithuanian). Excerpt reprinted in English translation as "The principles of arithmetic, presented by a new method"in van Heijenoort 1976, pp. 83–97.
- Richard, Jules (1905). "Les principes des mathématiques et le problème des ensembles". Revue Générale des Sciences Pures et Appliquées (in French). 16: 541. Reprinted in English translation as "The principles of mathematics and the problems of sets" in van Heijenoort 1976, pp. 142–144.
- Skolem, Thoralf (1920). "Logisch-kombinatorische Untersuchungen über die Erfüllbarkeit oder Beweisbarkeit mathematischer Sätze nebst einem Theoreme über dichte Mengen". Videnskapsselskapet Skrifter, I. Matematisk-naturvidenskabelig Klasse (in German). 6: 1–36.
Soare, Robert Irving (22 December 2011). "Computability Theory and Applications: The Art of Classical Computability" (PDF). Department of Mathematics. University of Chicago. Retrieved 23 August 2017. Swineshead, Richard (1498). Calculationes Suiseth Anglici (in Lithuanian). Papie: Per Franciscum Gyrardengum.
- Tarski, Alfred (1948). A decision method for elementary algebra and geometry. Santa Monica CA: RAND Corporation.
- .
- Weyl, Hermann (1918). Das Kontinuum. Kritische Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Analysis (in German). Leipzig.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) - S2CID 124189935. Reprinted in English translation as "Proof that every set can be well-ordered" in van Heijenoort 1976, pp. 139–141.
- S2CID 119924143. Reprinted in English translation as "A new proof of the possibility of a well-ordering" in van Heijenoort 1976, pp. 183–198.
- S2CID 120085563.
External links
- "Mathematical logic", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]
- Polyvalued logic and Quantity Relation Logic
- forall x: an introduction to formal logic, a free textbook by P. D. Magnus.
- A Problem Course in Mathematical Logic, a free textbook by Stefan Bilaniuk.
- Detlovs, Vilnis, and Podnieks, Karlis (University of Latvia), Introduction to Mathematical Logic. (hyper-textbook).
- In the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
- In the London Philosophy Study Guide:
- School of Mathematics, University of Manchester, Prof. Jeff Paris’s Mathematical Logic (course material and unpublished papers)