Logical positivism
Part of a series on |
Philosophy |
---|
![]() |
Logical positivism, also known as logical empiricism or neo-positivism, was a philosophical movement, in the
Logical positivism's central thesis was the verification principle, also known as the "verifiability criterion of meaning", according to which a statement is cognitively meaningful only if it can be verified through empirical observation or if it is a tautology (true by virtue of its own meaning or its own logical form).[2] The verifiability criterion thus rejected statements of metaphysics, theology, ethics and aesthetics as cognitively meaningless in terms of truth value or factual content. Despite its ambition to overhaul philosophy by mimicking the structure and process of empirical science, logical positivism became erroneously stereotyped as an agenda to regulate the scientific process and to place strict standards on it.[1]
The movement emerged in the late 1920s among
By the 1950s, problems identified within logical positivism's central tenets became seen as intractable, drawing escalating criticism among leading philosophers, notably from
Origins
Logical positivism emerged in
The logical positivist program established its theoretical foundations in the
History
Vienna and Berlin Circles
The
Early in the movement, Carnap, Hahn, Neurath and others recognised that the
Both Schlick and Carnap had been influenced by and sought to define logical positivism versus the neo-Kantianism of
Anglosphere
As the movement's first emissary to the
By the late 1930s, many in the movement had replaced
Post-war period
Following the
Principles
Verification and Confirmation
Verifiability Criterion of Meaning
According to the
Revisions to the criterion
Logical positivists in the Vienna Circle recognised quickly that the verifiability criterion was too restrictive.[13] Specifically, universal statements were noted to be empirically unverifiable, rendering vital domains of science and reason, such as scientific hypothesis, cognitively meaningless under verificationism. This would pose significant problems for the logical positivist program, absent revisions to its criterion of meaning.[27]
In his 1936 and 1937 papers, Testability and Meaning,
In his 1936 book, Language, Truth and Logic, A. J. Ayer distinguished strong and weak verification. He stipulated that, "A proposition is said to be verifiable, in the strong sense of the term, if, and only if, its truth could be conclusively established by experience", but is verifiable in the weak sense "if it is possible for experience to render it probable". He would add that, "no proposition, other than a tautology, can possibly be anything more than a probable hypothesis". Thus, he would conclude that all are open to weak verification.[30]
Analytic-synthetic distinction
In
The Vienna Circle rejected Kant's conception of synthetic a priori knowledge given its incompatibility with the
Observation-theory distinction
Early in his research, Carnap postulated that correspondence rules could be used to define theoretical terms from observation terms, contending that scientific knowledge could be unified by
By reconstructing the
Logicism
By
Carnap's early anti-metaphysical works employed Russell's
Philosophy of science
The logical positivist movement shed much of its revolutionary zeal following the defeat of Nazism and the decline of rival philosophies that sought radical reform, notably
Scientific explanation
The DN model ignores causal mechanisms beyond the principle of constant conjunction ("first event A and then always event B") in accordance with the Humean empiricist postulate that, though sequences of events are observable, the underpinning causal principles are not.[47] Hempel stated that well-formulated natural laws (empirically confirmed regularities) are satisfactory in approximating causal explanation.[48]
Hempel later proposed a probabilistic model of scientific explanation: The inductive-statistical (IS) model. Derivation of statistical laws from other statistical laws would further be designated as the deductive-statistical (DS) model. The DN and IS models are collectively referred to as the "covering law model" or "subsumption theory", the latter referring to the movement's stated goals of "theory reduction".[48][51]
Unity of science
Logical positivists were committed to the vision of a
The movement envisioned a universal scientific language that could express statements with common
Criticism
In the post-war period, key tenets of logical positivism, including the
Karl Popper
Karl Popper, a graduate of the University of Vienna, was an outspoken critic of the logical positivist movement from its inception. In Logik der Forschung (1934, published in English in 1959 as The Logic of Scientific Discovery) he attacked verificationism directly, contending that the problem of induction renders it impossible for scientific hypotheses and other universal statements to be verified conclusively. Any attempt to do so, he argued, would commit the fallacy of affirming the consequent, given that verification cannot—in itself—exclude alternative valid explanations for a specific phenomenon or instance of observation.[58] He would later affirm that the content of the verifiability criterion cannot be empirically verified, thus is meaningless by its own proposition and ultimately self-defeating as a principle.[59]
In the same book, Popper proposed falsifiability, which he presented, not as a criterion of cognitive meaning like verificationism (as commonly misunderstood),[60] but as a criterion to distinguish scientific from non-scientific statements, thereby to demarcate the boundaries of science. Popper observed that, though universal statements cannot be verified, they can be falsified, and that the most productive scientific theories were apparently those that carried the greatest 'predictive risks' of being falsified by observation.[61] He would conclude that the scientific method should be a hypothetico-deductive model, wherein scientific hypotheses must be falsifiable (per his criterion), held as provisionally true until proven false by observation, and are corroborated by supporting evidence rather than verified or confirmed.[62]
In rejecting neo-positivist views of cognitive meaningfulness, Popper considered
Willard V. O. Quine
In his influential 1951 paper Two Dogmas of Empiricism, American philosopher and logicist Willard Van Orman Quine challenged the analytic-synthetic distinction. Specifically, Quine examined the concept of analyticity, determining that all attempts to explain the idea reduce ultimately to circular reasoning. He would conclude that, if analyticity is untenable, so too is the neo-positivist proposition to redefine its boundaries.[63] Yet Carnap's reconstruction of analyticity was necessary for logic and mathematics to be deemed meaningful under verificationism. Quine's arguments encompassed numerous criticisms on this topic he had articulated to Carnap since 1933.[64] His work effectively pronounced the verifiability criterion untenable, threatening to uproot the broader logical positivist project.[65]
Norwood Hanson
In 1958,
Thomas Kuhn
Though foundationalism was often considered a constituent doctrine of logical positivism (and Kuhn's thesis an
In some sense, Kuhn's book unified science, but through historical and social assessment rather than by networking the scientific specialties using epistemological or linguistic models.[73] His ideas were adopted quickly by scholars in non-scientific disciplines, such as the social sciences in which neo-positivists were dominant,[46] ushering academia into postpositivism or postempiricism.[73]
Hilary Putnam
In his critique of the
Putnam advocated scientific realism, whereby scientific theory describes a real world existing independently of the senses. He rejected positivism, which he dismissed as a form of metaphysical idealism, in that it precluded any possibility to acquire knowledge of the unobservable aspects of nature. He also spurned instrumentalism, according to which a scientific theory is judged, not by whether it corresponds to reality, but by the extent to which it allows empirical predictions or resolves conceptual problems.[17]
Decline and legacy
In 1967,
In a 1976 interview,
Logical positivism's fall reopened the debate over the metaphysical merit of scientific theory, whether it can offer knowledge of the world beyond human experience (scientific realism) or whether it is simply an instrument to predict human experience (instrumentalism).[81][82] Philosophers increasingly critiqued the movement's doctrine and history, often misrepresenting it without thorough examination,[83] sometimes reducing it to oversimplifications and stereotypes, such as its association with foundationalism.[84]
See also
- Definitions of philosophy – Proposed definitions of philosophy
- Anti-realism – Truth of a statement rests on its demonstrability, not its correspondence to an external reality
- Sociological positivism– Empiricist philosophical theory
- Academic skepticism – Skeptical period of ancient Academy
- The Structure of Science – 1961 book by Ernest Nagel
- Raven paradox – Paradox arising from the question of what constitutes evidence for a statement
- Unobservable – Entity not directly observable by humans
People
- Ernst Mach – Austrian physicist, philosopher and university educator (1838–1916)
- Gottlob Frege – German philosopher, logician, and mathematician (1848–1925)
- Friedrich Waismann – Austrian mathematician, physicist and philosopher (1896–1959)
- Gustav Bergmann – Austrian-born American philosopher (1906-1987)
- Herbert Feigl – Austrian-American philosopher
- Kurt Grelling – German logician and philosopher (1886–1942)
- R. B. Braithwaite – English philosopher and ethicist (1900–1990)
References
- ^ LCCN 85030366.
- OCLC 748357235.
- ^ a b c Uebel, Thomas (2008). "Vienna Circle". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2024 ed.). Retrieved 27 February 2025.
- ^ a b c Hanfling, Oswald (1996). "Logical positivism". In Stuart G Shanker (ed.). Philosophy of Science, Logic and Mathematics in the Twentieth Century. Routledge. pp. 193–94.
- ^ Suppe, Frederick (1999). "The Positivist Model of Scientific Theories". In Robert Klee (ed.). Scientific Inquiry. Oxford University Press. pp. 16–24.
- ^ a b c Uebel 2008 3.7
- ^ Flew, Antony G (1984). "Science: Conjectures and refutations". In Andrew Bailey (ed.). A Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: St Martin's Press. p. 156.
- ISBN 978-0-631-23020-5. Retrieved 19 October 2023.
- ^ Leahey, Thomas H. (1980). "The Myth of Operationism". The Journal of Mind and Behavior. 1 (2): 127–143.
- ^ Tractatus Proposition 4.024 bears resemblance to Schlick's statement, "To state the circumstances under which a proposition is true is the same as stating its meaning".
- . English translation in: Sarkar, Sahotra, ed. (1996). Logical Empiricism at its Peak: Schlick, Carnap, and Neurath. New York: Garland Publishing. p. 38.
- ^ Rand, Rose (1933). Entwicklung der Thesen des "Wiener Kreises".
- ^ a b c Fetzer, James (2012). "Carl Hempel". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2012 ed.). Retrieved 31 August 2012.
- ISSN 0048-3893.
- ^ ISBN 978-0415939270.
- ^ Uebel 2008 3.1
- ^ a b c d e f Friedman 1999 p. xii
- ISBN 978-0-429-23433-0.
- ^ Uebel 2008 2.1
- LCCN 85030366.
- ^ LCCN lc96004399.as metaphysical nonsense. Although it has never been practiced consistently in the advanced natural sciences and has been criticized by many philosophers, notably Popper (1959, 1963), logical positivism remains the tacit philosophy of many scientists.
However, neo-positivism failed dismally to give a faithful account of science, whether natural or social. It failed because it remained anchored to sense-data and to a phenomenalist metaphysics, overrated the power of induction and underrated that of hypothesis, and denounced realism and materialism
- ^ Hempel, Carl G (1950). "Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning". Revue Internationale de Philosophie. 41: 41–63.
- ^ Various different views are discussed in Ayer's Language, Truth, and Logic, Schlick's "Positivism and realism" (reprinted in Sarkar 1996 and Ayer 1959) and Carnap's Philosophy and Logical Syntax.
- Ministry of Truth, will do what Carnap wants philosophical grammar to do.
- ^ Schlick, Moritz (1992). "The future Of philosophy". In Richard Rorty (ed.). The Linguistic Turn. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 43–53.
- ^ Ayer, A.J (1936). Language, Truth, and Meaning. pp. 2, 63–77.
- ^ John Vicker (2011). "The problem of induction". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 ed.). Retrieved 24 August 2012.
This initial formulation of the criterion was soon seen to be too strong; it counted as meaningless not only metaphysical statements but also statements that are clearly empirically meaningful, such as that all copper conducts electricity and, indeed, any universally quantified statement of infinite scope, as well as statements that were at the time beyond the reach of experience for technical, and not conceptual, reasons, such as that there are mountains on the back side of the moon.
- ^ Murzi, Mauro (2001). "Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ Crupi, Vincenzo (2021). "Confirmation". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 ed.). Retrieved 10 July 2023.
- ^ Ayer 1936 pp. 50–51
- ^ Rey, Georges (2023). "The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction". In Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2023 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 10 July 2023.
- ^ "Quine, Willard Van Orman: Analytic/Synthetic Distinction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 10 July 2023.
- ISBN 978-0-312-20923-0.
- ISBN 978-0-495-80896-1.
- ^ Rohlf, Michael (2010). "Immanuel Kant". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2024 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 February 2025.
- ^ De Pierris, Graciela; Friedman, Michael (2008). "Kant and Hume on Causality". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2024 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 February 2025.
- ^ Uebel 2008 2.3
- ISBN 978-0812693447.
- ISBN 978-0262263290.
- ^ a b Leitgeb, Hannes; Carus, André (2020). "Supplement to "Rudolf Carnap": E. The Reconstruction of Scientific Theories". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 4 February 2025.
- ^ a b Winnie, John A. (1967). "The Implicit Definition of Theoretical Terms". J. Phil. Sci. 18: 223–229.
- .
- ISBN 978-1-003-55703-6.
- ^ a b Hintikka, Jaako (2009). "Logicism". In Andrew D Irvine (ed.). Philosophy of Mathematics. Burlington MA: North Holland. pp. 283–84.
- . Reprinted in Ayer, Alfred Jules (1959). Logical Positivism. New York: Free Press. pp. 60–81.
- ^ a b Novick, Peter (1988). That Noble Dream. Cambridge University Press. p. 546.
- ^ a b Woodward, James. "Scientific explanation". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 ed.).
- ^ a b c d e Frederick Suppe, Frederick (1977). The Structure of Scientific Theories (2nd ed.). University of Illinois Press. pp. 619–21.
- ^ Montuschi, Eleonora (2003). Objects in Social Science. Continuum. pp. 61–62.
- ^ Bechtel, William (1988). Philosophy of Science: An Overview for Cognitive Science. Hillsdale NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Assoc. pp. 25–28.
- ^ Riedel, Manfred (1976). "Causal and Historical Explanation". In Manninen J; Tuomela R. (eds.). Essays on Explanation and Understanding: Studies in the Foundation of Humanities and Social Sciences. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing. pp. 3–4.
- doi:10.1086/508113.
- ISBN 978-0-226-45808-3.
- ISBN 978-3-476-05728-0.
- ISBN 978-1-003-24957-3.
- LCCN lc82012903.
- ^ Franco, Paul L. (2018). "Ordinary Language Criticisms of Logical Positivism". HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science. 8 (1): 157–190.
- ^ Okasha, Samir (2002). The Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 23.
- ^ Shea, Brendan. "Karl Popper: Philosophy of Science". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 12 May 2019.
- ^ Hacohen, Malachi Haim (2000). Karl Popper: The Formative Years, 1902–1945: Politics and Philosophy in Interwar Vienna. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 212–13.
- ^ a b Popper, Karl (1962). Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (2nd ed.). Routledge. pp. 34–37.
- .
- ^ Quine, Willard V. O. (1951). "Two Dogmas of Empiricism". Philosophical Review. 60: 20–43. collected in Quine, Willard V. O. (1953). From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
- ^ Rocknak, Stefanie. "Willard Van Orman Quine: The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 14 July 2024.
- ^ Shieh, Sanford (2012). "Logical Positivism and Quine". In D. Graff Fara; G. Russell (eds.). A Companion to the Philosophy of Language. Routledge. pp. 869–872.
- ^ Caldwell, Bruce (1994). Beyond Positivism: Economic Methodology in the 20th Century. London: Routledge. pp. 47–48.
- ^ Boyd, Nora Mills (2009). "Theory and Observation in Science". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2021 ed.). Retrieved 29 January 2025.
- ^ Okasha, Samir (2002). "Scientific Change and Scientific Revolutions". Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- ISSN 0899-2363.
- ^ Uebel 2008 3.3
- ISBN 978-0521041119.
- ^ Uebel 2008 3.3 Uebel writes, "Even Schlick conceded, however, that all scientific statements were fallible ones, so his position on foundationalism was by no means the traditional one. The point of his “foundations” remained less than wholly clear and different interpretation of it have been put forward."
- ^ a b Novick 1988 pp. 526–27
- ^ Putnam, Hilary (1962). "What Theories are Not". In E. Nagel; P. Suppes; A. Tarski (eds.). Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science. Stanford: Stanford University Press. pp. 240–251.
- ^ Putnam, Hilary (1999). "Problems with the observational/theoretical distinction". In Robert Klee (ed.). Scientific Inquiry. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 25–29.
- ^ Andreas, Holger (2013). "Theoretical Terms in Science". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (August 2021 ed.). Retrieved 30 January 2025.
- ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0.
- ISBN 978-0-8135-3107-6.
- ^ Chapman, Siobhan (2009). "Logical positivism". In Siobhan Chapman; Christopher Routledge (eds.). Key ideas in linguistics and the philosophy of language. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
- ^ "Ayer on Logical Positivism: Section 4". YouTube. 6:30.
- ^ Putnam, Hilary (1984). "What is realism?". In Jarrett Leplin (ed.). Scientific Realism. University of California Press. p. 140.
- .
- ^ Friedman 1999 p. 1
- ^ Friedman 1999 p. 2
Further reading
- Achinstein, Peter; Barker, Stephen F. (1969). The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.
- Bergmann, Gustav (1954). The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism. New York: Longmans Green.
- Cirera, Ramon (1994). Carnap and the Vienna Circle: Empiricism and Logical Syntax. Atlanta, GA: Rodopi.
- Creath, Richard. "Logical Empiricism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Gadol, Eugene T. (1982). Rationality and Science: A Memorial Volume for Moritz Schlick in Celebration of the Centennial of his Birth. Wien: Springer.
- Giere, Ronald N.; Richardson, Alan W. (1997). Origins of Logical Empiricism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
- Hájek, Alan. "Interpretations of Probability". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Holt, Jim (2017). "Positive Thinking". The New York Review of Books. 64 (20): 74–76.
- Jangam, R. T. (1970). Logical Positivism and Politics. Delhi: Sterling Publishers.
- Janik, Allan; Toulmin, Stephen (1973). Wittgenstein's Vienna. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
- Kraft, Victor (1953). The Vienna Circle: The Origin of Neo-positivism, a Chapter in the History of Recent Philosophy. New York: Greenwood Press.
- McGuinness, Brian (1979). Joachim Schulte; Brian McGuinness (eds.). Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations Recorded by Friedrich Waismann. New York: Barnes & Noble Books.
- Milkov, Nikolay, ed. (2015). Die Berliner Gruppe. Texte zum Logischen Empirismus von Walter Dubislav, Kurt Grelling, Carl G. Hempel, Alexander Herzberg, Kurt Lewin, Paul Oppenheim und Hans Reichenbach. Hamburg: Meiner.
- Mises von, Richard (1951). Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
- Murzi, Mauro (2007). "Logical Positivism". In Tom Flynn (ed.). The New Encyclopedia of Unbelief. Prometheus Books.
- Parrini, Paolo (1983). Empirismo logico e convenzionalismo: saggio di storia della filosofia della scienza. Milano: F. Angeli.
- Parrini, Paolo; Salmon, Wesley C.; Salmon, Merrilee H., eds. (2003). Logical Empiricism – Historical and Contemporary Perspectives. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
- Passmore, John (1967). "Logical Positivism". In Paul Edwards (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1st ed.). New York: Macmillan.
- Reisch, George (2005). How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: To the Icy Slopes of Logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.
- Rescher, Nicholas (1985). The Heritage of Logical Positivism. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
- Alan Richardson; Thomas Uebel, eds. (2007). The Cambridge Companion to Logical Positivism. New York: Cambridge University Press.
- Ryckman, Thomas A. "Early Philosophical Interpretations of General Relativity". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Salmon, Wesley; Wolters, Gereon, eds. (1994). Logic, Language, and the Structure of Scientific Theories: Proceedings of the Carnap-Reichenbach Centennial, University of Konstanz, 21–24 May 1991. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
- Sarkar, Sahotra, ed. (1996). The Emergence of Logical Empiricism: From 1900 to the Vienna Circle. New York: Garland Publishing.
- Sarkar, Sahotra, ed. (1996). Logical Empiricism and the Special Sciences: Reichenbach, Feigl, and Nagel. New York: Garland Publishing.
- Sarkar, Sahotra, ed. (1996). Decline and Obsolescence of Logical Empiricism: Carnap vs. Quine and the Critics. New York: Garland Publishing.
- Sarkar, Sahotra, ed. (1996). The Legacy of the Vienna Circle: Modern Reappraisals. New York: Garland Publishing.
- Spohn, Wolfgang, ed. (1991). Erkenntnis Orientated: A Centennial Volume for Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
- Stadler, Friedrich (2015). The Vienna Circle. Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism (2nd ed.). Dordrecht: Springer.
- Stadler, Friedrich, ed. (2003). The Vienna Circle and Logical Empiricism. Re-evaluation and Future Perspectives. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Werkmeister, William (May 1937). "Seven Theses of Logical Positivism Critically Examined". The Philosophical Review. 46 (3): 276–297. JSTOR 2181086.
External links
Media related to Logical positivism at Wikimedia Commons
Articles by logical positivists
- The Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle
- Carnap, Rudolf. 'The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language'
- Carnap, Rudolf. 'Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.'
- Excerpt from Carnap, Rudolf. Philosophy and Logical Syntax.
- Feigl, Herbert. 'Positivism in the Twentieth Century (Logical Empiricism)', Dictionary of the History of Ideas, 1974, Gale Group (Electronic Edition)
Articles on logical positivism