Structuralism (biology)

This is a good article. Click here for more information.
Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.

geometric transformation of one fish's body form into another with a 20° shear mapping. He does not discuss the evolutionary causes of such a structural change, and has accordingly been suspected of vitalism.[1]

Biological or process structuralism is a school of biological thought that objects to an exclusively

evolution is guided differently
, basically by more or less physical forces which shape the development of an animal's body, and sometimes implies that these forces supersede selection altogether.

Structuralists have proposed different mechanisms that might have guided the formation of

fossil record of most of the current phyla in the Cambrian explosion was "pre-Mendelian"[a] evolution caused by physical factors. Brian Goodwin, described by Wagner as part of "a fringe movement in evolutionary biology",[2] denies that biological complexity can be reduced to natural selection, and argues that pattern formation is driven by morphogenetic fields
.

Darwinian biologists have criticised structuralism, emphasising that there is plentiful evidence both that natural selection is effective and, from

evolutionary history. They accept that some structures such as the cell membrane
self-assemble, but deny the ability of self-organisation to drive large-scale evolution.

History

alternatives to Darwinism have been offered since the 19th century to explain how evolution took place, given that many scientists initially objected to natural selection. Many of these theories, including structural or developmental constraints, led (solid blue arrows) to some form of directed evolution (orthogenesis), with or without invoking divine control (dotted blue arrows). These theories were largely swept aside by the modern synthesis of genetics and natural selection in the early 20th century (dashed orange arrows).[3]

Geoffroy's law of compensation

In 1830, Étienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire argued a structuralist case against the functionalist (teleological) position of Georges Cuvier. Geoffroy believed that homologies of structure between animals indicated that they shared an ideal pattern; these did not imply evolution but a unity of plan, a law of nature.[b] He further believed that if one part was more developed within a structure, the other parts would necessarily be reduced in compensation, as nature always used the same materials: if more of them were used for one feature, less was available for the others.[4]

D'Arcy Thompson's morphology

In his "eccentric, beautiful"[5] 1917 book On Growth and Form, D'Arcy Wentworth Thompson revisited the old idea of "universal laws of form" to explain the observed forms of living organisms.[1] The science writer Philip Ball states that Thompson "presents mathematical principles as a shaping agency that may supersede natural selection, showing how the structures of the living world often echo those in inorganic nature", and notes his "frustration at the 'Just So' explanations of morphology offered by Darwinians." Instead, Ball writes, Thompson elaborates on how not heredity but physical forces govern biological form.[6] The philosopher of biology Michael Ruse similarly wrote that Thompson "had little time for natural selection", certainly preferring "mechanical explanations" and possibly straying into vitalism.[1]

Seilacher's pneu structures

Dickinsonia fossil described as a "pneu" structure with chambers inflated like a quilted air mattress. In Adolf Seilacher's structuralist view, the structure is determined mechanically by the need to distribute the tension across the surface, rather than having been guided by natural selection.

Like Thompson, the palaeontologist Adolf Seilacher emphasised fabricational constraints on form. He interpreted fossils such as Dickinsonia in the Ediacaran biota as "pneu" structures determined by mechanical inflation like a quilted air mattress, rather than having been driven by natural selection.[7][8]

Wagner's constraints on development

In his 2014 book Homology, Genes, and Evolutionary Innovation, the evolutionary biologist Günter P. Wagner argues for "the study of novelty as distinct from adaptation." He defines novelty as occurring when some part of the body develops an individual and quasi-independent existence, in other words as a distinct and recognisable structure, which he implies might occur before natural selection begins to adapt the structure for some function.[2][9] He forms a structuralist picture of evolutionary developmental biology, using empirical evidence, arguing that homology and biological novelty are key aspects requiring explanation, and that developmental bias (i.e. structural constraints on embryonic development) is a key explanation for these.[10][11]

Kauffman's self-organisation

Darwinists and structuralists agree that cell structures like the cell membrane spontaneously self-organize. They disagree on how important self-organization is in other areas of biology.

The mathematical biologist Stuart Kauffman suggested in 1993 that self-organization may play a role alongside natural selection in three areas of evolutionary biology, namely population dynamics, molecular evolution, and morphogenesis. With respect to molecular biology, Kauffman has been criticised for ignoring the role of energy in driving biochemical reactions in cells, which can fairly be called self-catalysing but which do not simply self-organise.[12]

Denton's 'Types'

The biochemist

universals".[c] Form is in this view not shaped by natural selection, but by "self-organizing properties of particular categories of matter" and by "cosmic fine-tuning of the laws of nature".[14] Denton has been criticised by the biochemist Laurence A. Moran as anti-Darwinian and favouring creationism.[15]

Gould and Lewontin's spandrels

Steven J. Gould and Richard Lewontin argued that the triangular area is a byproduct of the adaptation
of structures around it.

In 1979, influenced by Seilacher among others, the

pillars, as arches need (evolve) to be curved, and pillars need to be vertical. The resulting spandrels are exaptations, consequences of other evolutionary changes. Evolution, they argued, did not select for a protruding human chin: instead, reducing the length of the tooth row left the jaw protruding.[2]

Müller and Newman's pre-Mendelian evolution

Extreme structuralists like

Goodwin's morphogenetic fields

of chemical signals.

What Wagner calls "a fringe movement in evolutionary biology",[2] the form of structuralism exemplified by Brian Goodwin,[2][21] effectively denies that natural selection is important,[2][22] or at least that biological complexity could be reduced to natural selection.[22][23] This led to conflict with Darwinists such as Richard Dawkins.[24] Goodwin related the old concept of a morphogenetic field to the spatial distribution of chemical signals in a developing embryo.[25] He demonstrated with a mathematical model that a variety of patterns could be formed by choosing parameter values to set up either static geometric patterns or dynamic oscillations,[22][23] implying that the signalling system involved was somehow an alternative to natural selection.[15] Dawkins commented "He thinks he's anti-Darwinian, although he can't be, because he has no alternative explanation."[26]

Criticism

Laurence Moran notes that structuralism focuses mainly on animals, but that animals (emphasized) form only a small portion of the tree of life.[15]

While agreeing that pattern formation mechanisms such as those described by Goodwin exist, the biologists Richard Dawkins, Stephen J. Gould, Lynn Margulis, and Steve Jones have criticised Goodwin for suggesting that chemical signalling forms an alternative to natural selection.[15]

Moran, a "skeptical biochemist", comments that 'structuralism' is a "new buzzword ... guaranteed to impress the creationist crowd because nobody understands what it means but it sounds very 'sciency' and philosophical."[15] The philosopher of science Paul E. Griffiths writes that structuralists "view this structuring of the space of biological possibility as part of the fundamental physical structure of nature. But the phenomena of phylogenetic inertia and developmental constraint do not support this interpretation. These phenomena show that the evolutionary pathways available to an organism are a function of the developmental structure of the organism."[27]

Moran summarizes: "There's nothing in science that supports the views of the structuralists. We have perfectly good explanations for why bumblebees are different than mushrooms and why all vertebrates have vertebrae and not exoskeletons. There's no evidence to support the idea that if you replay the tape of life it will come out looking anything like what we see today. You can be confident that when you visit another planet you will not find vertebrates."[15]

The

Lewis Held wrote that "The notion that aspects of anatomy can be explained by physical forces (like expansion cracking) was advocated ~ 100 years earlier in D'Arcy Thompson's 1917 On Growth and Form and in Theodore Cook's 1914 book The Curves of Life.[d] Over the intervening century, various traits have been proposed to arise mechanically rather than genetically: brain convolutions, cartilage condensations, flower corrugations, tooth cusps, and fish otoliths. To this kooky list we can now add the crooked smile of the crocodile, or at least the cracked skin that surrounds it."[e][28]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Gregor Mendel pioneered the study of genetics.
  2. ^ In this, Geoffroy's homologies were like Aristotle's forms.
  3. Platonic realism.[13]
  4. ^ The artist Theodore Cook's The Curves of Life, Constable, 1914 to some extent anticipated D'Arcy Thompson, exploring spirals in art and nature.
  5. ^ Held's final point was that the cracks in the crocodile's skin are genuinely explained by cracking, unlike all the other examples he lists.[28]

References