Species

This is a good article. Click here for more information.
Source: Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia.

LifeDomainKingdomPhylumClassOrderFamilyGenusSpecies
The hierarchy of biological classification's eight major taxonomic ranks. A genus contains one or more species. Minor intermediate ranks are not shown.

A species (pl.: species) is often defined as the largest group of

paleontologists use the concept of the chronospecies since fossil
reproduction cannot be examined.

The most recent rigorous estimate for the total number of species of eukaryotes is between 8 and 8.7 million.[2][3][4] About 14% of these had been described by 2011.[4]

All species (except

zoological nomenclature). For example, Boa constrictor is one of the species of the genus Boa
, with constrictor being the species' epithet.

While the definitions given above may seem adequate at first glance, when looked at more closely they represent problematic

microspecies, and in a ring species. Also, among organisms that reproduce only asexually, the concept of a reproductive species breaks down, and each clone is potentially a microspecies. Although none of these are entirely satisfactory definitions, and while the concept of species may not be a perfect model of life, it is still a useful tool to scientists and conservationists for studying life on Earth, regardless of the theoretical difficulties. If species were fixed and clearly distinct from one another, there would be no problem, but evolutionary processes cause species to change. This obliges taxonomists to decide, for example, when enough change has occurred to declare that a lineage should be divided into multiple chronospecies, or when populations have diverged to have enough distinct character states to be described as cladistic
species.

Species and higher taxa were seen from the time of

Viruses are a special case, driven by a balance of mutation and selection, and can be treated as quasispecies
.

Definition

Biologists and taxonomists have made many attempts to define species, beginning from

ecospecies based on ecological niches (4) evolutionary species based on lineage (5) genetic species based on gene pool (6) morphospecies based on form or phenotype and (7) taxonomic species, a species as determined by a taxonomist.[9]

Typological or morphological species

All adult Eurasian blue tits share the same coloration, unmistakably identifying the morphospecies.[10]

A typological species is a group of organisms in which individuals conform to certain fixed properties (a type), so that even pre-literate people often recognise the same taxon as do modern taxonomists.[11][12] The clusters of variations or phenotypes within specimens (such as longer or shorter tails) would differentiate the species. This method was used as a "classical" method of determining species, such as with Linnaeus, early in evolutionary theory. However, different phenotypes are not necessarily different species (e.g. a four-winged Drosophila born to a two-winged mother is not a different species). Species named in this manner are called morphospecies.[13][14]

In the 1970s, Robert R. Sokal, Theodore J. Crovello and Peter Sneath proposed a variation on the morphological species concept, a phenetic species, defined as a set of organisms with a similar phenotype to each other, but a different phenotype from other sets of organisms.[15] It differs from the morphological species concept in including a numerical measure of distance or similarity to cluster entities based on multivariate comparisons of a reasonably large number of phenotypic traits.[16]

Recognition and cohesion species

A mate-recognition species is a group of sexually reproducing organisms that recognise one another as potential mates.[17][18] Expanding on this to allow for post-mating isolation, a cohesion species is the most inclusive population of individuals having the potential for phenotypic cohesion through intrinsic cohesion mechanisms; no matter whether populations can hybridise successfully, they are still distinct cohesion species if the amount of hybridisation is insufficient to completely mix their respective gene pools.[19] A further development of the recognition concept is provided by the biosemiotic concept of species.[20]

Genetic similarity and barcode species

Barcode of Life Data Systems
database.

In microbiology, genes can move freely even between distantly related bacteria, possibly extending to the whole bacterial domain. As a rule of thumb, microbiologists have assumed that members of Bacteria or Archaea with 16S ribosomal RNA gene sequences more similar than 97% to each other need to be checked by DNA–DNA hybridisation to decide if they belong to the same species.[21] This concept was narrowed in 2006 to a similarity of 98.7%.[22]

The

average nucleotide identity (ANI) method quantifies genetic distance between entire genomes, using regions of about 10,000 base pairs. With enough data from genomes of one genus, algorithms can be used to categorize species, as for Pseudomonas avellanae in 2013,[23] and for all sequenced bacteria and archaea since 2020.[24] Observed ANI values among sequences appear to have an "ANI gap" at 85–95%, suggesting that a genetic boundary suitable for defining a species concept is present.[25]

Genetic introgression mediated by endosymbionts and other vectors can further make barcodes ineffective in the identification of species.[30]

Phylogenetic or cladistic species

The cladistic or phylogenetic species concept is that a species is the smallest lineage which is distinguished by a unique set of either genetic or morphological traits. No claim is made about reproductive isolation, making the concept useful also in palaeontology where only fossil evidence is available.

A phylogenetic or

red list and can attract conservation legislation and funding.[42]

Unlike the biological species concept, a cladistic species does not rely on reproductive isolation – its criteria are independent of processes that are integral in other concepts.[31] Therefore, it applies to asexual lineages.[36][37] However, it does not always provide clear cut and intuitively satisfying boundaries between taxa, and may require multiple sources of evidence, such as more than one polymorphic locus, to give plausible results.[37]

Evolutionary species

An evolutionary species, suggested by George Gaylord Simpson in 1951, is "an entity composed of organisms which maintains its identity from other such entities through time and over space, and which has its own independent evolutionary fate and historical tendencies".[8][43] This differs from the biological species concept in embodying persistence over time. Wiley and Mayden stated that they see the evolutionary species concept as "identical" to Willi Hennig's species-as-lineages concept, and asserted that the biological species concept, "the several versions" of the phylogenetic species concept, and the idea that species are of the same kind as higher taxa are not suitable for biodiversity studies (with the intention of estimating the number of species accurately). They further suggested that the concept works for both asexual and sexually-reproducing species.[44] A version of the concept is Kevin de Queiroz's "General Lineage Concept of Species".[45]

Ecological species

An ecological species is a set of organisms adapted to a particular set of resources, called a niche, in the environment. According to this concept, populations form the discrete phenetic clusters that we recognise as species because the ecological and evolutionary processes controlling how resources are divided up tend to produce those clusters.[46]

Genetic species

A genetic species as defined by Robert Baker and Robert Bradley is a set of genetically isolated interbreeding populations. This is similar to Mayr's Biological Species Concept, but stresses genetic rather than reproductive isolation.

allozymes (enzyme variants).[48]

Evolutionarily significant unit

An evolutionarily significant unit (ESU) or "wildlife species"[49] is a population of organisms considered distinct for purposes of conservation.[50]

Chronospecies

A chronospecies is defined in a single lineage (solid line) whose morphology changes with time. At some point, palaeontologists judge that enough change has occurred that two species (A and B), separated in time and anatomy, once existed.

In

palaeontology, with only comparative anatomy (morphology) and histology[51] from fossils as evidence, the concept of a chronospecies can be applied. During anagenesis (evolution, not necessarily involving branching), some palaeontologists seek to identify a sequence of species, each one derived from the phyletically extinct one before through continuous, slow and more or less uniform change. In such a time sequence, some palaeontologists assess how much change is required for a morphologically distinct form to be considered a different species from its ancestors.[52][53][54][55]

Viral quasispecies

Viruses have enormous populations, are doubtfully living since they consist of little more than a string of DNA or RNA in a protein coat, and mutate rapidly. All of these factors make conventional species concepts largely inapplicable.

mutagenic environment, and hence governed by a mutation–selection balance. It is predicted that a viral quasispecies at a low but evolutionarily neutral and highly connected (that is, flat) region in the fitness landscape will outcompete a quasispecies located at a higher but narrower fitness peak in which the surrounding mutants are unfit, "the quasispecies effect" or the "survival of the flattest". There is no suggestion that a viral quasispecies resembles a traditional biological species.[57][58][59] The International Committee on Taxonomy of Viruses has since 1962 developed a universal taxonomic scheme for viruses; this has stabilised viral taxonomy.[60][61][62]

Mayr's biological species concept

Biological Species Concept
of reproductive isolation in 1942.

Most modern textbooks make use of

Biological Species Concept as a basis for further discussion on the definition of species. It is also called a reproductive or isolation concept. This defines a species as[65]

groups of actually or potentially interbreeding natural populations, which are reproductively isolated from other such groups.[65]

It has been argued that this definition is a natural consequence of the effect of sexual reproduction on the dynamics of natural selection.[66][67][68][69] Mayr's use of the adjective "potentially" has been a point of debate; some interpretations exclude unusual or artificial matings that occur only in captivity, or that involve animals capable of mating but that do not normally do so in the wild.[65]

The species problem

It is difficult to define a species in a way that applies to all organisms.[70] The debate about species concepts is called the species problem.[65][71][72][73] The problem was recognised even in 1859, when Darwin wrote in On the Origin of Species:

No one definition has satisfied all naturalists; yet every naturalist knows vaguely what he means when he speaks of a species. Generally the term includes the unknown element of a distinct act of creation.[74]

When Mayr's concept breaks down

Palaeontologists are limited to morphological evidence when deciding whether fossil life-forms like these Inoceramus
bivalves formed a separate species.

Many authors have argued that a simple textbook definition, following Mayr's concept, works well for most

multi-celled organisms
, but breaks down in several situations:

Willow warbler
Chiffchaff
The willow warbler and chiffchaff are almost identical in appearance but do not interbreed.

Species identification is made difficult by discordance between molecular and morphological investigations; these can be categorised as two types: (i) one morphology, multiple lineages (e.g.

cryptic species) and (ii) one lineage, multiple morphologies (e.g. phenotypic plasticity, multiple life-cycle stages).[84] In addition, horizontal gene transfer (HGT) makes it difficult to define a species.[85] All species definitions assume that an organism acquires its genes from one or two parents very like the "daughter" organism, but that is not what happens in HGT.[86] There is strong evidence of HGT between very dissimilar groups of prokaryotes, and at least occasionally between dissimilar groups of eukaryotes,[85] including some crustaceans and echinoderms.[87]

The evolutionary biologist James Mallet concludes that

there is no easy way to tell whether related geographic or temporal forms belong to the same or different species. Species gaps can be verified only locally and at a point of time. One is forced to admit that Darwin's insight is correct: any local reality or integrity of species is greatly reduced over large geographic ranges and time periods.[19]

The botanist

East African Great Lakes.[90] Wilkins argued that "if we were being true to evolution and the consequent phylogenetic approach to taxa, we should replace it with a 'smallest clade' idea" (a phylogenetic species concept).[91] Mishler and Wilkins [92] and others [93] concur with this approach, even though this would raise difficulties in biological nomenclature. Wilkins cited the ichthyologist Charles Tate Regan's early 20th century remark that "a species is whatever a suitably qualified biologist chooses to call a species".[91] Wilkins noted that the philosopher Philip Kitcher called this the "cynical species concept",[94] and arguing that far from being cynical, it usefully leads to an empirical taxonomy for any given group, based on taxonomists' experience.[91] Other biologists have gone further and argued that we should abandon species entirely, and refer to the "Least Inclusive Taxonomic Units" (LITUs),[95] a view that would be coherent with current evolutionary theory.[93]

Aggregates of microspecies

The species concept is further weakened by the existence of

fly agaric.[103]

  • Blackberries belong to any of hundreds of microspecies of the Rubus fruticosus species aggregate.
    Blackberries belong to any of hundreds of microspecies of the
    species aggregate
    .
  • The butterfly genus Heliconius contains many similar species.
    The butterfly genus Heliconius contains many similar species.
  • The Hypsiboas calcaratus–fasciatus species complex contains at least six species of treefrog.
    The
    fasciatus
    species complex contains at least six species of treefrog.

Hybridisation

Natural hybridisation presents a challenge to the concept of a reproductively isolated species, as fertile hybrids permit gene flow between two populations. For example, the carrion crow Corvus corone and the hooded crow Corvus cornix appear and are classified as separate species, yet they can hybridise where their geographical ranges overlap.[104]

Ring species

A

Ensatina eschscholtzii group of 19 populations of salamanders in America,[107] and the greenish warbler in Asia,[108] but many so-called ring species have turned out to be the result of misclassification leading to questions on whether there really are any ring species.[109][110][111][112]

  • Seven "species" of Larus gulls interbreed in a ring around the Arctic.
    Seven "species" of Larus gulls interbreed in a ring around the Arctic.
  • Opposite ends of the ring: a herring gull (Larus argentatus) (front) and a lesser black-backed gull (Larus fuscus) in Norway
    Opposite ends of the ring: a herring gull (
    Larus fuscus
    ) in Norway
  • A greenish warbler, Phylloscopus trochiloides
    A greenish warbler, Phylloscopus trochiloides
  • Presumed evolution of five "species" of greenish warblers around the Himalayas
    Presumed
    Himalayas

Taxonomy and naming

Puma concolor
.

Common and scientific names

The commonly used names for kinds of organisms are often ambiguous: "cat" could mean the domestic cat,

Puma concolor in various parts of America, while "panther" may also mean the jaguar (Panthera onca) of Latin America or the leopard (Panthera pardus) of Africa and Asia. In contrast, the scientific names of species are chosen to be unique and universal (except for some inter-code homonyms); they are in two parts used together: the genus as in Puma, and the specific epithet as in concolor.[113][114]

Species description

The type specimen (holotype) of Lacerta plica, described by Linnaeus in 1758

A species is given a taxonomic name when a type specimen is described formally, in a publication that assigns it a unique scientific name. The description typically provides means for identifying the new species, which may not be based solely on morphology[115] (see cryptic species), differentiating it from other previously described and related or confusable species and provides a validly published name (in botany) or an available name (in zoology) when the paper is accepted for publication. The type material is usually held in a permanent repository, often the research collection of a major museum or university, that allows independent verification and the means to compare specimens.[116][117][118] Describers of new species are asked to choose names that, in the words of the International Code of Zoological Nomenclature, are "appropriate, compact, euphonious, memorable, and do not cause offence".[119]

Abbreviations

Books and articles sometimes intentionally do not identify species fully, using the abbreviation "sp." in the singular or "spp." (standing for species pluralis, Latin for "multiple species") in the plural in place of the specific name or epithet (e.g. Canis sp.). This commonly occurs when authors are confident that some individuals belong to a particular genus but are not sure to which exact species they belong, as is common in paleontology.[120]

Authors may also use "spp." as a short way of saying that something applies to many species within a genus, but not to all. If scientists mean that something applies to all species within a genus, they use the genus name without the specific name or epithet. The names of

italics. However, abbreviations such as "sp." should not be italicised.[120]

When a species' identity is not clear, a specialist may use "cf." before the epithet to indicate that confirmation is required. The abbreviations "nr." (near) or "aff." (affine) may be used when the identity is unclear but when the species appears to be similar to the species mentioned after.[120]

Identification codes

With the rise of online databases, codes have been devised to provide identifiers for species that are already defined, including:

Lumping and splitting

The naming of a particular species, including which genus (and higher taxa) it is placed in, is a hypothesis about the evolutionary relationships and distinguishability of that group of organisms. As further information comes to hand, the hypothesis may be corroborated or refuted. Sometimes, especially in the past when communication was more difficult, taxonomists working in isolation have given two distinct names to individual organisms later identified as the same species. When two species names are discovered to apply to the same species, the older species name is given

synonymy. Dividing a taxon into multiple, often new, taxa is called splitting. Taxonomists are often referred to as "lumpers" or "splitters" by their colleagues, depending on their personal approach to recognising differences or commonalities between organisms.[125][126][120] The circumscription of taxa, considered a taxonomic decision at the discretion of cognizant specialists, is not governed by the Codes of Zoological or Botanical Nomenclature, in contrast to the PhyloCode, and contrary to what is done in several other fields, in which the definitions of technical terms, like geochronological units and geopolitical entities, are explicitly delimited.[127][93]

Broad and narrow senses

The

antonym sensu lato ("in the broad sense") denotes a wider usage, for instance including other subspecies. Other abbreviations such as "auct." ("author"), and qualifiers such as "non" ("not") may be used to further clarify the sense in which the specified authors delineated or described the species.[120][128][129]

Change

Species are subject to change, whether by evolving into new species,[130] exchanging genes with other species,[131] merging with other species or by becoming extinct.[132]

Speciation

The

allopatric speciation, where populations are separated geographically and can diverge gradually as mutations accumulate. Reproductive isolation is threatened by hybridisation, but this can be selected against once a pair of populations have incompatible alleles of the same gene, as described in the Bateson–Dobzhansky–Muller model.[130] A different mechanism, phyletic speciation, involves one lineage gradually changing over time into a new and distinct form (a chronospecies), without increasing the number of resultant species.[136]

Exchange of genes between species

Horizontal gene transfers between widely separated species complicate the phylogeny of bacteria.

Horizontal gene transfer between organisms of different species, either through hybridisation, antigenic shift, or reassortment, is sometimes an important source of genetic variation. Viruses can transfer genes between species. Bacteria can exchange plasmids with bacteria of other species, including some apparently distantly related ones in different phylogenetic domains, making analysis of their relationships difficult, and weakening the concept of a bacterial species.[137][85][138][131]

Louis-Marie Bobay and Howard Ochman suggest, based on analysis of the genomes of many types of bacteria, that they can often be grouped "into communities that regularly swap genes", in much the same way that plants and animals can be grouped into reproductively isolated breeding populations. Bacteria may thus form species, analogous to Mayr's biological species concept, consisting of asexually reproducing populations that exchange genes by homologous recombination.[139][140]

Extinction

A species is extinct when the

climate change, and changes in oceanic and atmospheric chemistry, and they in turn had major effects on Earth's ecology, atmosphere, land surface and waters.[141][142] Another form of extinction is through the assimilation of one species by another through hybridization. The resulting single species has been termed as a "compilospecies".[143]

Practical implications

Biologists and conservationists need to categorise and identify organisms in the course of their work. Difficulty assigning organisms reliably to a species constitutes a threat to the validity of research results, for example making measurements of how abundant a species is in an ecosystem moot. Surveys using a phylogenetic species concept reported 48% more species and accordingly smaller populations and ranges than those using nonphylogenetic concepts; this was termed "taxonomic inflation",[144] which could cause a false appearance of change to the number of endangered species and consequent political and practical difficulties.[145][146] Some observers claim that there is an inherent conflict between the desire to understand the processes of speciation and the need to identify and to categorise.[146]

Conservation laws in many countries make special provisions to prevent species from going extinct. Hybridization zones between two species, one that is protected and one that is not, have sometimes led to conflicts between lawmakers, land owners and conservationists. One of the classic cases in North America is that of the protected

California spotted owl and the barred owl; this has led to legal debates.[147] It has been argued that the species problem is created by the varied uses of the concept of species, and that the solution is to abandon it and all other taxonomic ranks, and use unranked monophyletic groups instead, an approach facilitated by the PhyloCode. It has been argued, too, that since species are not comparable, counting them is not a valid measure of biodiversity; alternative measures of phylogenetic biodiversity have been proposed.[148][89][149]

History

Classical forms

In

family, and the crows a genus. A kind was distinguished by its attributes; for instance, a bird has feathers, a beak, wings, a hard-shelled egg, and warm blood. A form was distinguished by being shared by all its members, the young inheriting any variations they might have from their parents. Aristotle believed all kinds and forms to be distinct and unchanging. More importantly, in Aristotle's works, the terms γένος (génos) and εἶδος (eidos) are relative; a taxon that is considered an eidos in a given context can be considered a génos in another, and be further subdivided into eide (plural of eidos).[150][151] His approach remained influential until the Renaissance,[152] and still, to a lower extent, today.[153]

Fixed species

John Ray believed that species breed true and do not change, even though variations exist.
Carl Linnaeus created the binomial system for naming species.

When observers in the

Early Modern period began to develop systems of organization for living things, they placed each kind of animal or plant into a context. Many of these early delineation schemes would now be considered whimsical: schemes included consanguinity based on colour (all plants with yellow flowers) or behaviour (snakes, scorpions and certain biting ants). John Ray
, an English naturalist, was the first to attempt a biological definition of species in 1686, as follows:

No surer criterion for determining species has occurred to me than the distinguishing features that perpetuate themselves in propagation from seed. Thus, no matter what variations occur in the individuals or the species, if they spring from the seed of one and the same plant, they are accidental variations and not such as to distinguish a species ... Animals likewise that differ specifically preserve their distinct species permanently; one species never springs from the seed of another nor vice versa.[154]

In the 18th century, the Swedish scientist Carl Linnaeus classified organisms according to shared physical characteristics, and not simply based upon differences.[155] Like many contemporary systematists,[156][157][158] he established the idea of a taxonomic hierarchy of classification based upon observable characteristics and intended to reflect natural relationships.[159][160] At the time, however, it was still widely believed that there was no organic connection between species (except, possibly, between those of a given genus),[93] no matter how similar they appeared. This view was influenced by European scholarly and religious education, which held that the taxa had been created by God, forming an Aristotelian hierarchy, the scala naturae or great chain of being. However, whether or not it was supposed to be fixed, the scala (a ladder) inherently implied the possibility of climbing.[161]

Mutability

In viewing evidence of hybridisation, Linnaeus recognised that species were not fixed and could change; he did not consider that new species could emerge and maintained a view of divinely fixed species that may alter through processes of hybridisation or acclimatisation.[162] By the 19th century, naturalists understood that species could change form over time, and that the history of the planet provided enough time for major changes. Jean-Baptiste Lamarck, in his 1809 Zoological Philosophy, described the transmutation of species, proposing that a species could change over time, in a radical departure from Aristotelian thinking.[163]

In 1859, Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace provided a compelling account of evolution and the formation of new species. Darwin argued that it was populations that evolved, not individuals, by natural selection from naturally occurring variation among individuals.[164] This required a new definition of species. Darwin concluded that species are what they appear to be: ideas, provisionally useful for naming groups of interacting individuals, writing:

I look at the term species as one arbitrarily given for the sake of convenience to a set of individuals closely resembling each other ... It does not essentially differ from the word variety, which is given to less distinct and more fluctuating forms. The term variety, again, in comparison with mere individual differences, is also applied arbitrarily, and for convenience sake.[165]

See also

References

  1. ^ Zimmer, Carl (19 February 2024). "What Is a Species, Anyway? - Some of the best known species on Earth may not be what they seem". The New York Times. Archived from the original on 19 February 2024. Retrieved 19 February 2024.
  2. ISSN 0362-4331
    . Retrieved 25 January 2020.
  3. ^ Borenstein, S. (2019). "UN report: Humans accelerating extinction of other species". Associated Press.
  4. ^
    PMID 21886479
    .
  5. ^ a b "Species Concepts". Scientific American. 20 April 2012. Archived from the original on 14 March 2017. Retrieved 14 March 2017.
  6. PMID 21237047
    .
  7. .
  8. ^ a b Mayden, R. L. (1997). "A hierarchy of species concepts: the denouement of the species problem". In Claridge, M. F.; Dawah, H. A.; Wilson, M. R. (eds.). The Units of Biodiversity – Species in Practice Special Volume 54. Systematics Association.
  9. ^ Zachos 2016, p. 79.
  10. .
  11. .
  12. .
  13. .
  14. .
  15. ^ Claridge, Dawah & Wilson 1997, p. 404
  16. .
  17. ^ Claridge et al.:408–409.
  18. ^ Paterson, H. E. H. (1985). "Species and Speciation". In Vrba, E. S. (ed.). Monograph No. 4: The recognition concept of species. Pretoria: Transvaal Museum.
  19. ^ (PDF) from the original on 19 October 2016.
  20. from the original on 7 February 2018.
  21. .
  22. ^ Stackebrandt, E.; Ebers, J. (2006). "Taxonomic parameters revisited: tarnished gold standards" (PDF). Microbiology Today. 33 (4): 152–155. Archived (PDF) from the original on 25 March 2018.
  23. PMID 25722247. This article contains quotations from this source, which is available under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC BY 4.0) Archived 16 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine
    license.
  24. .
  25. .
  26. ^ "What Is DNA Barcoding?". Barcode of Life. Archived from the original on 1 July 2017. Retrieved 11 October 2017.
  27. PMID 18784790
    .
  28. ^ Stoeckle, Mark (November–December 2013). "DNA Barcoding Ready for Breakout". GeneWatch. 26 (5). Archived from the original on 3 April 2014. Retrieved 25 March 2018.
  29. PMID 16214748
    .
  30. .
  31. ^ .
  32. ^ Wheeler, Quentin D.; Platnick, Norman I. 2000. The phylogenetic species concept (sensu Wheeler & Platnick). In: Wheeler & Meier2000, pp. 55–69
  33. PMID 18346919
    .
  34. ..
  35. ^ Brower, Andrew V. Z. and Randall T. Schuh. (2021). Biological Systematics: Principles and Applications. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY.
  36. ^
    PMID 18346919
    .
  37. ^ .
  38. .
  39. ^ Zachos 2016, pp. 91–92.
  40. ^ Groves, C.; Grubb, P. 2011. Ungulate taxonomy. Baltimore, MD: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
  41. PMID 23362112
    .
  42. .
  43. .
  44. ^ Wheeler & Meier 2000, pp. 70–92, 146–160, 198–208
  45. ^ de Queiroz, Kevin (1998). "The general lineage concept of species, species criteria, and the process of speciation". In D. J. Howard; S. H. Berlocher (eds.). Endless forms: species and speciation. Oxford University Press. pp. 57–75.
  46. .
  47. .
  48. .
  49. ^ Government of Canada. Committee on the Status of Endangered Wildlife in Canada. "COSEWIC's Assessment Process and Criteria". Cosepac.gc.ca. Archived from the original on 12 April 2015. Retrieved 7 April 2015.
  50. ^ DeWeerdt, Sarah (29 July 2002). "What Really is an Evolutionarily Significant Unit?". University of Washington. Archived from the original on 5 February 2017. Retrieved 1 December 2016.
  51. .
  52. ^ "Chronospecies". Oxford Reference. Archived from the original on 1 October 2014. Retrieved 12 January 2018.
  53. ^ Carr, Steven M. (2005). "Evolutionary species and chronospecies". Memorial University Newfoundland and Labrador. Archived from the original on 10 March 2016. Retrieved 12 January 2018.
  54. ^ Dzik, J. (1985). "Typologic versus population concepts of chronospecies: implications for ammonite biostratigraphy" (PDF). Acta Palaeontologica Polonica. 30 (1–2): 71–92. Archived (PDF) from the original on 13 March 2017.
  55. from the original on 7 February 2018.
  56. .
  57. .
  58. .
  59. .
  60. from the original on 10 December 2017. Retrieved 13 April 2017.
  61. .
  62. .
  63. ^ Mayr, Ernst (1942). Systematics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia University Press.
  64. ^ Wheeler, pp. 17–29
  65. ^
    PMID 15851674
    .
  66. .
  67. .
  68. .
  69. .
  70. (PDF) from the original on 1 December 2016.
  71. .
  72. ^ "Darwin 1859 Chapter II, p. 59". Darwin-online.org.uk. Archived from the original on 21 October 2012. Retrieved 25 November 2012.
  73. S2CID 41706247
    .
  74. ^ Templeton, A. R. (1989). "The meaning of species and speciation: A genetic perspective". In Otte, D.; Endler, J. A. (eds.). Speciation and its Consequences. Sinauer Associates. pp. 3–27.
  75. from the original on 17 June 2013.
  76. .
  77. .
  78. .
  79. from the original on 14 March 2017.
  80. ^ Zachos 2016, p. 101.
  81. ^ Zachos 2016, pp. 156–157.
  82. PMID 25156897
    .
  83. ^ a b c Melcher, Ulrich (2001). "Molecular genetics: Horizontal gene transfer". Oklahoma State University. Archived from the original on 4 March 2016.
  84. PMID 15913459
    .
  85. .
  86. .
  87. ^ (PDF) from the original on 10 January 2018.
  88. .
  89. ^ .
  90. .
  91. ^ .
  92. . I defend a view of the species category, pluralistic realism, which is designed to do justice to the insights of many different groups of systematists.
  93. .
  94. ^ Heywood, V. H. (1962). "The 'species aggregate' in theory and practice". In Heywood, V. H.; Löve, Á. (eds.). Symposium on Biosystematics, Montreal, October 1962. pp. 26–36.
  95. from the original on 7 February 2018.
  96. .
  97. .
  98. .
  99. .
  100. .
  101. .
  102. ^ "Defining a species". University of California Berkeley. Archived from the original on 13 March 2017. Retrieved 12 March 2017.
  103. ^ Zachos 2016, p. 188.
  104. from the original on 12 March 2017.
  105. (PDF) from the original on 12 January 2018.
  106. .
  107. .
  108. .
  109. .
  110. .
  111. ^ "A Word About Species Names ..." Smithsonian Marine Station at Fort Pierce. Archived from the original on 24 March 2017. Retrieved 11 March 2017.
  112. ^ Hone, Dave (19 June 2013). "What's in a name? Why scientific names are important". The Guardian. Archived from the original on 15 February 2017. Retrieved 11 March 2017.
  113. S2CID 252562185
    .
  114. .
  115. ^ Nicholson, Dan H. "Botanical nomenclature, types, & standard reference works". Smithsonian National Museum of Natural History, Department of Botany. Archived from the original on 16 September 2015. Retrieved 17 November 2015.
  116. ^ "International Code of Zoological Nomenclature, Recommendation 25C". Archived from the original on 8 June 2011. Retrieved 18 June 2011.
  117. ^ a b c d e Winston, Judith E. (1999). Describing species. Practical taxonomic procedure for biologists. New York: Columbia University Press. pp. 141–144.
  118. ^ "Home – Taxonomy – NCBI". Ncbi.nlm.nih.gov. 19 October 2012. Archived from the original on 7 February 2018. Retrieved 25 November 2012.
  119. ^ "KEGG Organisms: Complete Genomes". Genome.jp. Archived from the original on 14 October 2012. Retrieved 25 November 2012.
  120. ^ "Taxonomy". Uniprot.org. Archived from the original on 27 November 2012. Retrieved 25 November 2012.
  121. ^ "ITIS: Homo sapiens". Catalogue of Life. Archived from the original on 12 March 2017. Retrieved 11 March 2017.
  122. ^ Simpson, George Gaylord (1945). "The Principles of Classification and a Classification of Mammals". Bulletin of the American Museum of Natural History. 85: 23.
  123. S2CID 201790420
    .
  124. .
  125. ^ Wilson, Philip (2016). "sensu stricto, sensu lato". AZ of tree terms. Archived from the original on 10 January 2018. Retrieved 9 January 2018.
  126. ^ "Glossary: sensu". International Commission on Zoological Nomenclature. Archived from the original on 2 August 2017. Retrieved 9 January 2018.
  127. ^
    PMID 20439284
    .
  128. ^ .
  129. ^ Zachos 2016, pp. 77–96.
  130. PMID 17789700
    .
  131. .
  132. .
  133. .
  134. ^ Pennisi, Elizabeth (2004). "Researchers Trade Insights about Gene Swapping" (PDF). Science. 334–335: 335. Archived from the original (PDF) on 18 February 2006.
  135. (PDF) from the original on 26 March 2009.
  136. .
  137. .
  138. from the original on 5 September 2015.
  139. .
  140. ^ Zachos 2016, p. 82.
  141. .
  142. (PDF) from the original on 11 January 2018.
  143. ^ .
  144. ^ Haig, Susan M.; Allendorf, F.W. (2006). "Hybrids and Policy". In Scott, J. Michael; Goble, D. D.; Davis, Frank W. (eds.). The Endangered Species Act at Thirty, Volume 2: Conserving Biodiversity in Human-Dominated Landscapes. Washington: Island Press. pp. 150–163. Archived from the original on 7 February 2018.
  145. ISSN 0006-3207
    .
  146. .
  147. .
  148. .
  149. .
  150. .
  151. .
  152. ^ Davis, P. H.; Heywood, V. H. (1973). Principles of Angiosperm Taxonomy. Huntington, NY: Robert E. Krieger Publishing Company. p. 17.
  153. ^ Magnol, Petrus (1689). Prodromus historiae generalis plantarum in quo familiae plantarum per tabulas disponuntur (in Latin). Pech. p. 79.
  154. ^ Tournefort, Joseph Pitton de (1656-1708) Auteur du texte (1694). Elemens de botanique, ou Methode pour connoître les plantes. I. [Texte.] / . Par Mr Pitton Tournefort... [T. I-III]. Paris: L’Imprimerie Royale. p. 562.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link)
  155. ^ Jussieu, Antoine-Laurent de (1789). Antonii Laurentii de Jussieu ... Genera plantarum secundum ordines naturales disposita: juxta methodum in horto regio Parisiensi exaratam, anno M.DCC.LXXIV. (in Latin). Apud viduam Herissant, typographum, viâ novâ B.M. sub signo Crucis Aureæ. Et Theophilum Barrois, ad ripam Augustinianorum. p. 498.
  156. .
  157. ^ Simpson, George Gaylord (1961). Principles of Animal Taxonomy. Columbia University Press. pp. 56–57.
  158. JSTOR 2709555
    .
  159. ^ "Carl Linnaeus (1707–1778)". UCMP Berkeley. Archived from the original on 30 April 2011. Retrieved 24 January 2018.
  160. .
  161. .
  162. .

Sources

External links